The self in such a schizoid
organization is usually more or less
unembodied. It is experienced as a
mental entity. It enters the
condition called
by Kierkegaard 'shutupness'. The
individual's actions are not felt as
expressions of his self. His
actions, all that David called his
'personality' and which I have
proposed to call his false-self
system, become dissociated and
partly autonomous. The self is
not felt to participate in the
doings of the false self or selves,
and all its or their actions are felt
to be increasingly false and futile.
The self, on the other hand, shut
up with itself, regards itself as the
'true' self and the persona as
false. The individual complains of
futility, of lack of spontaneity, but
he may be cultivating his lack of
spontaneity and thus aggravating
his sense of futility. He says he is
not real and is outside reality and
not properly alive. Existentially,
he is quite right. The self is
extremely aware of itself, and
observes the false self, usually
highly critically. It is characteristic
of the organization of a false self
or persona, on the other hand,
that one way in which it is usually
incomplete is in its very imperfect
reflective awareness. But the self
may feel itself in danger from the
overall spread of the false-self
system or from one particular
part of it (cf. David's dread of
female impersonation). The
individual in this position is
invariably terrifyingly
'selfconscious ' (see Chapter 7) in
the sense in which this word is
used to mean the exact opposite,
namely, the feeling of being
under observation by the other.
These changes in the relationship
between the different aspects of
the person's relation to himself
are constantly associated with his
inter-personal relationships.
These are complex and never
quite the same from person to
person. The individual's
self-relationship becomes a
pseudo-interpersonal one, and
the self treats the false selves as
though they were other people
whom it depersonalizes. David,
for instance, referring to a part he
played which he found was
disliked, said: 'It had a nasty
tongue.' From within, the self now
looks out at the false things being
said and done and detests the
speaker and doer as though he
were someone else. In all this
there is an attempt to create
relationships to persons and
things within the individual
without recourse to the outer
world of persons and things at
all. The individual is developing a
microcosmos within himself; but,
of course, this autistic, private,
intra-individual 'world' is not a
feasible substitute for the only
world there really is, the shared
The embodied and unembodied
self 75 world. If this were a
feasible project then there would
be no need for psychosis. Such a
schizoid individual in one sense is
trying to be omnipotent by
enclosing within his own being,
without recourse to a creative
relationship with others, modes
of relationship that require the
effective presence to him of other
people and of the outer world. He
would appear to be, in an unreal,
impossible way, all persons and
things to himself. The imagined
advantages are safety for the true
self, isolation and hence freedom
from others, self-sufficiency, and
control. The actual disadvantages
that can be mentioned at this
point are that this project is
impossible and, being a false
hope, leads on to persistent
despair; secondly, a persistent,
haunting sense of futility is the
equally inevitable outcome, since
the hidden shut-up self, in
disowning participation (except,
as David's case, by appearing as
another persona) in the
quasi-autonomous activities of
the falseself systems, is living
only 'mentally'. Moreover, this
shut-up self, being isolated, is
unable to be enriched by outer
experience, and so the whole
inner world comes to be more and
more impoverished, until the
individual may come to feel he is
merely a vacuum. The sense of
being able to do anything and the
feeling of possessing everything
then exist side by side with a
feeling of impotence and
emptiness. The individual who
may at one time have felt
predominantly 'outside' the life
going on there, which he affects
to despise as petty and
commonplace compared to the
richness he has here, inside
himself, now longs to get inside
life again, and get life inside
himself, so dreadful is his inner
deadness. The crucial feature of
the schizoid individual of this type
that we have to understand is the
nature of the anxieties to which
he is subject. We have already
outlined some of the forms these
anxieties take under the terms
engulfment, implosion, and the
dread of losing inner autonomy,
freedom; in short, being turned
from a man with subjectivity to a
thing, a mechanism, a stone, an
it, being petrified. We have yet to
study how these anxieties are
potentiated by the development
of the schizoid organization.
When the self partially abandons
the body and its acts, and
withdraws into mental activity, it
experiences itself as an entity
perhaps localized somewhere in
the body. We have suggested
that 76 The Divided Self this
withdrawal is in part an effort to
preserve its being, since
relationship of any kind with
others is experienced as a threat
to the self's identity. The self feels
safe only in hiding, and isolated.
Such a self can, of course, be
isolated at any time whether
other people are present or not.
But this does not work. No one
feels more 'vulnerable', more
liable to be exposed by the look
of another person than the
schizoid individual. If he is not
acutely aware of being seen by
others ('self-conscious'), he has
temporarily avoided his anxiety
becoming manifest by one or
other of two methods. Either he
turns the other person into a
thing, and depersonalizes or
objectifies his own feelings
towards this thing, or he affects
indifference. The
depersonalization of the person
and/or the attitude of indifference
are closely related but not quite
identical. The depersonalized
person can be used,
manipulated, acted upon. As we
stated above (Chapter 1), the
essential feature of a thing as
opposed to a person is that a
thing has no subjectivity of its
own, and hence can have no
reciprocal intentions. In the
attitude of indifference the person
or thing is treated with
casualness, or callousness, as
though he or it did not matter,
ultimately as though he or it did
not exist. A person minus
subjectivity can still be
important. A thing can still
matter a great deal. Indifference
denies to persons and to things
their significance. Petrification, we
remember, was one of Perseus's
methods of killing his enemies. By
means of the eyes in Medusa's
head, he turned them into
stones. Petrification is one way of
killing. Of course, to feel that
another person is treating or
regarding one not as a person
but as a thing need not itself be
frightening if one is sufficiently
sure of one's own existence.
Thus, being a thing in someone
else's eyes does not represent to
the 'normal' person a catastrophic
threat, but to the schizoid
individual every pair of eyes is in
a Medusa's head which he feels
has power actually to kill or
deaden something precariously
vital in him. He tries therefore to
forestall his own petrification by
turning others into stones. By
doing this he feels he can achieve
some measure of safety.
Generally speaking, the schizoid
individual is not erecting
defences against the loss of a
part of his body. His whole effort
is rather to preserve his self.
This, as we have pointed out, is
pre- The embodied and
unembodied self 77 cariously
established; he is subject to the
dread of his own dissolution into
non-being, into what William
Blake described in the last resort
as 'chaotic non-entity'. His
autonomy is threatened with
engulfment. He has to guard
himself against losing his
subjectivity and sense of being
alive. In so far as he feels empty,
the full, substantial, living reality
of others is an impingement
which is always liable to get out
of hand and become implosive,
threatening to overwhelm and
obliterate his self completely as a
gas will obliterate a vacuum, or as
water will gush in and entirely fill
an empty dam. The schizoid
individual fears a real live
dialectical relationship with real
live people. He can relate himself
only to depersonalized persons,
to phantoms of his own
phantasies (imagos), perhaps to
things, perhaps to animals. We
suggest, therefore, that the
schizoid state we are describing
can be understood as an attempt
to preserve a being that is
precariously structured. We shall
suggest later that the initial
structuralization of being into its
basic elements occurs in early
infancy. In normal circumstances,
this occurs in such a way as to be
so conclusively stable in its basic
elements (for instance, the
continuity of time, the distinction
between the self and not-self,
phantasy and reality), that it can
henceforth be taken for granted:
on this stable base, a
considerable amount of plasticity
can exist in what we call a
person's 'character'. In the
schizoid character structure, on
the other hand, there is an
insecurity in the laying down of
the foundations and a
compensatory rigidity in the
superstructure. If the whole of the
individual's being cannot be
defended, the individual retracts
his lines of defence until he
withdraws within a central
citadel. He is prepared to write off
everything he is, except his 'self'.
But the tragic paradox is that the
more the self is defended in this
way, the more it is destroyed. The
apparent eventual destruction
and dissolution of the self in
schizophrenic conditions is
accomplished not by external
attacks from the enemy (actual
or supposed), from without, but
by the devastation caused by the
inner defensive manoeuvres
themselves. 5 The inner self in
the schizoid condition You can
hold yourself back from the
sufferings of the world, this is
something you are free to do and
is in accord with your nature, but
perhaps precisely this holding
back is the only suffering that you
might be able to avoid. FRANZ
KAFKA In the schizoid condition
here described there is a
persistent scission between the
self and the body. What the
individual regards as his true self
is experienced as more or less
disembodied, and bodily
experience and actions are in turn
felt to be part of the false-self
system. It is now necessary to
consider the two elements in this
split in more detail, and also the
relationship of the one to the
other. First, we consider the
mental or unembodied self. It is
well known that temporary states
of dissociation of the self from the
body occur in normal people. In
general, one can say that it is a
response that appears to be
available to most people who find
themselves enclosed within a
threatening experience from
which there is no physical
escape. Prisoners in concentration
camps tried to feel that way, for
the camp offered no possible way
out either spatially or at the end
of a period of time. The only way
out was by a psychical
withdrawal 'into' one's self and
'out of the body. This dissociation
is characteristically associated
with such thoughts as 'This is like
a dream', 'This seems unreal', 'I
can't believe this is true', 'Nothing
seemed to be touching me', 'I
cannot take it in', 'This is not
happening to me', i.e. with
feelings of estrangement and
derealization. The body may go
on acting in an outwardly normal
way, but inwardly it is felt to be
acting on its own, automatically.
However, despite the
dream-nature or unreality of
experience, and the automatic
nature of action, the self is at the
same time far from 'sleepy';
indeed, it is excessively alert, and
may be thinking and observing
with exceptional lucidity. The
inner self in the schizoid condition
79 The temporary estrangement
of the self from the body may be
represented in dreams. A girl of
nineteen, the date of whose
marriage was fast approaching, a
marriage she had come to dread
for various reasons, dreamed that
she was in the back seat of a car,
which was driving itself. This girl
was not a basically schizoid
person but was reacting by a
schizoid defence to a particular
situation. R. had a dream shortly
before starting treatment. He was
on the footplate of a bus. The bus
had no driver. He jumped off and
the bus went on to crash. One is
tempted to regard a dream he
had after four months of
psychotherapy as a measure of
some change in a desirable
direction. 'I am running after a
bus. Suddenly I'm on the
footplate of the bus, and at the
same time, I'm running after it. I'm
trying to join up with myself on
the bus but I can't entirely catch
up on the bus. I felt frightened at
this.' One could multiply
instances of this common
experience of temporary
dissociation. Sometimes it is
intentionally induced; more
often, it occurs without the
individual's control. But in the
patients here considered, the
splitting is not simply a
temporary reaction to a specific
situation of great danger, which is
reversible when the danger is
past. It is, on the contrary, a basic
orientation to life, and if it is
followed back through their lives
one usually finds that they seem,
in fact, to have emerged from the
early months of infancy with this
split already under way. The
'normal' individual, in a situation
all can see to be threatening to
his being and to offer no real
sense of escape, develops a
schizoid state in trying to get
outside it, if not physically, at
least mentally: he becomes a
mental observer, who looks on,
detached and impassive, at what
his body is doing or what is being
done to his body. If this is so in
the 'normal', it is at least possible
to suppose that the individual
whose abiding mode of
being-in-the-world is of this split
nature is living in what to him, if
not to us, is a world that
threatens his being from all
sides, and from which there is no
exit. This is indeed the case for
such people. For them the world
is a prison without bars, a
concentration camp without
barbed wire. The paranoic has
specific persecutors. Someone is
against him. There is a plot on
foot to steal his brains. A machine
is concealed in the wall of his
bedroom which emits mind rays
to soften his brain, 80 The
Divided Self or to send electric
shocks through him while he is
asleep. The person I am
describing feels at this phase
persecuted by reality itself. The
world as it is, and other people as
they are, are the dangers. The
self then seeks by being
unembodied to transcend the
world and hence to be safe. But a
self is liable to develop which
feels it is outside all experience
and activity. It becomes a
vacuum. Everything is there,
outside; nothing is here, inside.
Moreover, the constant dread of
all that is there, of being
overwhelmed, is potentiated
rather than mitigated by the need
to keep the world at bay. Yet the
self may at the same time long
more than anything for
participation in the world. Thus,
its greatest longing is felt as its
greatest weakness and giving in
to this weakness is its greatest
dread, since in participation the
individual fears that his vacuum
will be obliterated, that he will be
engulfed or otherwise lose his
identity, which has come to be
equated with the maintenance of
the transcendence of the self
even though this is a
transcendence in avoid. This
detachment of the self means
that the self is never revealed
directly in the individual's
expressions and actions, nor does
it experience anything
spontaneously or immediately.
The self's relationship to the
other is always at one remove.
The direct and immediate
transactions between the
individual, the other, and the
world, even in such basic
respects as perceiving and
acting, all come to be
meaningless, futile, and false.
One can represent the alternative
state of affairs schematically as
shown opposite. Objects
perceived by the self are
experienced as real. Thoughts
and feelings of which the self is
the agent are alive and are felt to
have point. Actions to which the
self is committed are felt as
genuine. If the individual
delegates all transactions
between himself and the other to
a system within his being which
is not 'him', then the world is
experienced as unreal, and all
that belongs to this system is felt
to be false, futile, and
meaningless. Everyone is subject
to a certain extent at one time or
another to such moods of futility,
meaninglessness, and
purposelessness, but in schizoid
individuals these moods are
particularly insistent. These
moods arise from the fact that the
doors of perception and/or the 82
The Divided Self gates of action
are not in the command of the
self but are being lived and
operated by a false self. The
unrealness of perceptions and the
falsity and meaninglessness of all
activity are the necessary
consequences of perception and
activity being in the command of
a false self- a system partially
dissociated from the 'true' self,
which is, therefore, excluded from
direct participation in the
individual's relatedness with
other persons and the world. A
pseudo-duality is thus
experienced in the individual's
own being. Instead of the
individual meeting the world with
an integral selfhood, he disavows
part of his own being along' with
his disavowal of immediate
attachment to things and people
in the world. This can be
represented schematically as
follows: Instead of (self/body)
other the situation is self
(body-other) The self, therefore, is
precluded from having a direct
relationship with real things and
real people. When this has
happened in patients, one is
witness to the struggle which
ensues to preserve the self's own
sense of its own realness,
aliveness, and identity. In the
first scheme, one has a benign
circle. The reality of the world and
of the self are mutually
potentiated by the direct
relationship between self and
other. In Figure 2, there is a
vicious circle. Every element in
this diagram comes to be
experienced as more and more
unreal and dead. Love is
precluded and dread takes its
place. The final effect is an
overall experience of everything
having come to a stop. Nothing
moves; nothing is alive;
everything is dead, including the
self. The self by its detachment is
precluded from a full experience
of realness and aliveness. What
one might call a creative
relationship with the other, in
which there is mutual enrichment
of the self and the other (benign
circle), is impossible, and an
interaction is substituted which
may seem to operate efficiently
and smoothly for a while but
which has no 'life' in it (sterile
relationship). There is a quasi-it-it
interaction instead of an I-thou
relationship. This interaction is a
dead process. The inner self
seeks to live by certain
(apparently) compensating
advantages. Such a self cherishes
certain ideals. One, which was
The Divided Self condition called
by Kierkegaard 'shutupness'. The
individual's actions are not felt as
expressions of his self. His
actions, all that David called his
'personality' and which I have
proposed to call his false-self
system, become dissociated and
partly autonomous. The self is
not felt to participate in the
doings of the false self or selves,
and all its or their actions are felt
to be increasingly false and futile.
The self, on the other hand, shut
up with itself, regards itself as the
'true' self and the persona as
false. The individual complains of
futility, of lack of spontaneity, but
he may be cultivating his lack of
spontaneity and thus aggravating
his sense of futility. He says he is
not real and is outside reality and
not properly alive. Existentially,
he is quite right. The self is
extremely aware of itself, and
observes the false self, usually
highly critically. It is characteristic
of the organization of a false self
or persona, on the other hand,
that one way in which it is usually
incomplete is in its very imperfect
reflective awareness. But the self
may feel itself in danger from the
overall spread of the false-self
system or from one particular
part of it (cf. David's dread of
female impersonation). The
individual in this position is
invariably terrifyingly
'selfconscious ' (see Chapter 7) in
the sense in which this word is
used to mean the exact opposite,
namely, the feeling of being
under observation by the other.
These changes in the relationship
between the different aspects of
the person's relation to himself
are constantly associated with his
inter-personal relationships.
These are complex and never
quite the same from person to
person. The individual's
self-relationship becomes a
pseudo-interpersonal one, and
the self treats the false selves as
though they were other people
whom it depersonalizes. David,
for instance, referring to a part he
played which he found was
disliked, said: 'It had a nasty
tongue.' From within, the self now
looks out at the false things being
said and done and detests the
speaker and doer as though he
were someone else. In all this
there is an attempt to create
relationships to persons and
things within the individual
without recourse to the outer
world of persons and things at
all. The individual is developing a
microcosmos within himself; but,
of course, this autistic, private,
intra-individual 'world' is not a
feasible substitute for the only
world there really is, the shared
The embodied and unembodied
self 75 world. If this were a
feasible project then there would
be no need for psychosis. Such a
schizoid individual in one sense is
trying to be omnipotent by
enclosing within his own being,
without recourse to a creative
relationship with others, modes
of relationship that require the
effective presence to him of other
people and of the outer world. He
would appear to be, in an unreal,
impossible way, all persons and
things to himself. The imagined
advantages are safety for the true
self, isolation and hence freedom
from others, self-sufficiency, and
control. The actual disadvantages
that can be mentioned at this
point are that this project is
impossible and, being a false
hope, leads on to persistent
despair; secondly, a persistent,
haunting sense of futility is the
equally inevitable outcome, since
the hidden shut-up self, in
disowning participation (except,
as David's case, by appearing as
another persona) in the
quasi-autonomous activities of
the falseself systems, is living
only 'mentally'. Moreover, this
shut-up self, being isolated, is
unable to be enriched by outer
experience, and so the whole
inner world comes to be more and
more impoverished, until the
individual may come to feel he is
merely a vacuum. The sense of
being able to do anything and the
feeling of possessing everything
then exist side by side with a
feeling of impotence and
emptiness. The individual who
may at one time have felt
predominantly 'outside' the life
going on there, which he affects
to despise as petty and
commonplace compared to the
richness he has here, inside
himself, now longs to get inside
life again, and get life inside
himself, so dreadful is his inner
deadness. The crucial feature of
the schizoid individual of this type
that we have to understand is the
nature of the anxieties to which
he is subject. We have already
outlined some of the forms these
anxieties take under the terms
engulfment, implosion, and the
dread of losing inner autonomy,
freedom; in short, being turned
from a man with subjectivity to a
thing, a mechanism, a stone, an
it, being petrified. We have yet to
study how these anxieties are
potentiated by the development
of the schizoid organization.
When the self partially abandons
the body and its acts, and
withdraws into mental activity, it
experiences itself as an entity
perhaps localized somewhere in
the body. We have suggested
that 76 The Divided Self this
withdrawal is in part an effort to
preserve its being, since
relationship of any kind with
others is experienced as a threat
to the self's identity. The self feels
safe only in hiding, and isolated.
Such a self can, of course, be
isolated at any time whether
other people are present or not.
But this does not work. No one
feels more 'vulnerable', more
liable to be exposed by the look
of another person than the
schizoid individual. If he is not
acutely aware of being seen by
others ('self-conscious'), he has
temporarily avoided his anxiety
becoming manifest by one or
other of two methods. Either he
turns the other person into a
thing, and depersonalizes or
objectifies his own feelings
towards this thing, or he affects
indifference. The
depersonalization of the person
and/or the attitude of indifference
are closely related but not quite
identical. The depersonalized
person can be used,
manipulated, acted upon. As we
stated above (Chapter 1), the
essential feature of a thing as
opposed to a person is that a
thing has no subjectivity of its
own, and hence can have no
reciprocal intentions. In the
attitude of indifference the person
or thing is treated with
casualness, or callousness, as
though he or it did not matter,
ultimately as though he or it did
not exist. A person minus
subjectivity can still be
important. A thing can still
matter a great deal. Indifference
denies to persons and to things
their significance. Petrification, we
remember, was one of Perseus's
methods of killing his enemies. By
means of the eyes in Medusa's
head, he turned them into
stones. Petrification is one way of
killing. Of course, to feel that
another person is treating or
regarding one not as a person
but as a thing need not itself be
frightening if one is sufficiently
sure of one's own existence.
Thus, being a thing in someone
else's eyes does not represent to
the 'normal' person a catastrophic
threat, but to the schizoid
individual every pair of eyes is in
a Medusa's head which he feels
has power actually to kill or
deaden something precariously
vital in him. He tries therefore to
forestall his own petrification by
turning others into stones. By
doing this he feels he can achieve
some measure of safety.
Generally speaking, the schizoid
individual is not erecting
defences against the loss of a
part of his body. His whole effort
is rather to preserve his self.
This, as we have pointed out, is
pre- The embodied and
unembodied self 77 cariously
established; he is subject to the
dread of his own dissolution into
non-being, into what William
Blake described in the last resort
as 'chaotic non-entity'. His
autonomy is threatened with
engulfment. He has to guard
himself against losing his
subjectivity and sense of being
alive. In so far as he feels empty,
the full, substantial, living reality
of others is an impingement
which is always liable to get out
of hand and become implosive,
threatening to overwhelm and
obliterate his self completely as a
gas will obliterate a vacuum, or as
water will gush in and entirely fill
an empty dam. The schizoid
individual fears a real live
dialectical relationship with real
live people. He can relate himself
only to depersonalized persons,
to phantoms of his own
phantasies (imagos), perhaps to
things, perhaps to animals. We
suggest, therefore, that the
schizoid state we are describing
can be understood as an attempt
to preserve a being that is
precariously structured. We shall
suggest later that the initial
structuralization of being into its
basic elements occurs in early
infancy. In normal circumstances,
this occurs in such a way as to be
so conclusively stable in its basic
elements (for instance, the
continuity of time, the distinction
between the self and not-self,
phantasy and reality), that it can
henceforth be taken for granted:
on this stable base, a
considerable amount of plasticity
can exist in what we call a
person's 'character'. In the
schizoid character structure, on
the other hand, there is an
insecurity in the laying down of
the foundations and a
compensatory rigidity in the
superstructure. If the whole of the
individual's being cannot be
defended, the individual retracts
his lines of defence until he
withdraws within a central
citadel. He is prepared to write off
everything he is, except his 'self'.
But the tragic paradox is that the
more the self is defended in this
way, the more it is destroyed. The
apparent eventual destruction
and dissolution of the self in
schizophrenic conditions is
accomplished not by external
attacks from the enemy (actual
or supposed), from without, but
by the devastation caused by the
inner defensive manoeuvres
themselves. 5 The inner self in
the schizoid condition You can
hold yourself back from the
sufferings of the world, this is
something you are free to do and
is in accord with your nature, but
perhaps precisely this holding
back is the only suffering that you
might be able to avoid. FRANZ
KAFKA In the schizoid condition
here described there is a
persistent scission between the
self and the body. What the
individual regards as his true self
is experienced as more or less
disembodied, and bodily
experience and actions are in turn
felt to be part of the false-self
system. It is now necessary to
consider the two elements in this
split in more detail, and also the
relationship of the one to the
other. First, we consider the
mental or unembodied self. It is
well known that temporary states
of dissociation of the self from the
body occur in normal people. In
general, one can say that it is a
response that appears to be
available to most people who find
themselves enclosed within a
threatening experience from
which there is no physical
escape. Prisoners in concentration
camps tried to feel that way, for
the camp offered no possible way
out either spatially or at the end
of a period of time. The only way
out was by a psychical
withdrawal 'into' one's self and
'out of the body. This dissociation
is characteristically associated
with such thoughts as 'This is like
a dream', 'This seems unreal', 'I
can't believe this is true', 'Nothing
seemed to be touching me', 'I
cannot take it in', 'This is not
happening to me', i.e. with
feelings of estrangement and
derealization. The body may go
on acting in an outwardly normal
way, but inwardly it is felt to be
acting on its own, automatically.
However, despite the
dream-nature or unreality of
experience, and the automatic
nature of action, the self is at the
same time far from 'sleepy';
indeed, it is excessively alert, and
may be thinking and observing
with exceptional lucidity. The
inner self in the schizoid condition
79 The temporary estrangement
of the self from the body may be
represented in dreams. A girl of
nineteen, the date of whose
marriage was fast approaching, a
marriage she had come to dread
for various reasons, dreamed that
she was in the back seat of a car,
which was driving itself. This girl
was not a basically schizoid
person but was reacting by a
schizoid defence to a particular
situation. R. had a dream shortly
before starting treatment. He was
on the footplate of a bus. The bus
had no driver. He jumped off and
the bus went on to crash. One is
tempted to regard a dream he
had after four months of
psychotherapy as a measure of
some change in a desirable
direction. 'I am running after a
bus. Suddenly I'm on the
footplate of the bus, and at the
same time, I'm running after it. I'm
trying to join up with myself on
the bus but I can't entirely catch
up on the bus. I felt frightened at
this.' One could multiply
instances of this common
experience of temporary
dissociation. Sometimes it is
intentionally induced; more
often, it occurs without the
individual's control. But in the
patients here considered, the
splitting is not simply a
temporary reaction to a specific
situation of great danger, which is
reversible when the danger is
past. It is, on the contrary, a basic
orientation to life, and if it is
followed back through their lives
one usually finds that they seem,
in fact, to have emerged from the
early months of infancy with this
split already under way. The
'normal' individual, in a situation
all can see to be threatening to
his being and to offer no real
sense of escape, develops a
schizoid state in trying to get
outside it, if not physically, at
least mentally: he becomes a
mental observer, who looks on,
detached and impassive, at what
his body is doing or what is being
done to his body. If this is so in
the 'normal', it is at least possible
to suppose that the individual
whose abiding mode of
being-in-the-world is of this split
nature is living in what to him, if
not to us, is a world that
threatens his being from all
sides, and from which there is no
exit. This is indeed the case for
such people. For them the world
is a prison without bars, a
concentration camp without
barbed wire. The paranoic has
specific persecutors. Someone is
against him. There is a plot on
foot to steal his brains. A machine
is concealed in the wall of his
bedroom which emits mind rays
to soften his brain, 80 The
Divided Self or to send electric
shocks through him while he is
asleep. The person I am
describing feels at this phase
persecuted by reality itself. The
world as it is, and other people as
they are, are the dangers. The
self then seeks by being
unembodied to transcend the
world and hence to be safe. But a
self is liable to develop which
feels it is outside all experience
and activity. It becomes a
vacuum. Everything is there,
outside; nothing is here, inside.
Moreover, the constant dread of
all that is there, of being
overwhelmed, is potentiated
rather than mitigated by the need
to keep the world at bay. Yet the
self may at the same time long
more than anything for
participation in the world. Thus,
its greatest longing is felt as its
greatest weakness and giving in
to this weakness is its greatest
dread, since in participation the
individual fears that his vacuum
will be obliterated, that he will be
engulfed or otherwise lose his
identity, which has come to be
equated with the maintenance of
the transcendence of the self
even though this is a
transcendence in avoid. This
detachment of the self means
that the self is never revealed
directly in the individual's
expressions and actions, nor does
it experience anything
spontaneously or immediately.
The self's relationship to the
other is always at one remove.
The direct and immediate
transactions between the
individual, the other, and the
world, even in such basic
respects as perceiving and
acting, all come to be
meaningless, futile, and false.
One can represent the alternative
state of affairs schematically as
shown opposite. Objects
perceived by the self are
experienced as real. Thoughts
and feelings of which the self is
the agent are alive and are felt to
have point. Actions to which the
self is committed are felt as
genuine. If the individual
delegates all transactions
between himself and the other to
a system within his being which
is not 'him', then the world is
experienced as unreal, and all
that belongs to this system is felt
to be false, futile, and
meaningless. Everyone is subject
to a certain extent at one time or
another to such moods of futility,
meaninglessness, and
purposelessness, but in schizoid
individuals these moods are
particularly insistent. These
moods arise from the fact that the
doors of perception and/or the 82
The Divided Self gates of action
are not in the command of the
self but are being lived and
operated by a false self. The
unrealness of perceptions and the
falsity and meaninglessness of all
activity are the necessary
consequences of perception and
activity being in the command of
a false self- a system partially
dissociated from the 'true' self,
which is, therefore, excluded from
direct participation in the
individual's relatedness with
other persons and the world. A
pseudo-duality is thus
experienced in the individual's
own being. Instead of the
individual meeting the world with
an integral selfhood, he disavows
part of his own being along' with
his disavowal of immediate
attachment to things and people
in the world. This can be
represented schematically as
follows: Instead of (self/body)
other the situation is self
(body-other) The self, therefore, is
precluded from having a direct
relationship with real things and
real people. When this has
happened in patients, one is
witness to the struggle which
ensues to preserve the self's own
sense of its own realness,
aliveness, and identity. In the
first scheme, one has a benign
circle. The reality of the world and
of the self are mutually
potentiated by the direct
relationship between self and
other. In Figure 2, there is a
vicious circle. Every element in
this diagram comes to be
experienced as more and more
unreal and dead. Love is
precluded and dread takes its
place. The final effect is an
overall experience of everything
having come to a stop. Nothing
moves; nothing is alive;
everything is dead, including the
self. The self by its detachment is
precluded from a full experience
of realness and aliveness. What
one might call a creative
relationship with the other, in
which there is mutual enrichment
of the self and the other (benign
circle), is impossible, and an
interaction is substituted which
may seem to operate efficiently
and smoothly for a while but
which has no 'life' in it (sterile
relationship). There is a quasi-it-it
interaction instead of an I-thou
relationship. This interaction is a
dead process. The inner self
seeks to live by certain
(apparently) compensating
advantages. Such a self cherishes
certain ideals. One, which was
The Divided Self condition called
by Kierkegaard 'shutupness'. The
individual's actions are not felt as
expressions of his self. His
actions, all that David called his
'personality' and which I have
proposed to call his false-self
system, become dissociated and
partly autonomous. The self is
not felt to participate in the
doings of the false self or selves,
and all its or their actions are felt
to be increasingly false and futile.
The self, on the other hand, shut
up with itself, regards itself as the
'true' self and the persona as
false. The individual complains of
futility, of lack of spontaneity, but
he may be cultivating his lack of
spontaneity and thus aggravating
his sense of futility. He says he is
not real and is outside reality and
not properly alive. Existentially,
he is quite right. The self is
extremely aware of itself, and
observes the false self, usually
highly critically. It is characteristic
of the organization of a false self
or persona, on the other hand,
that one way in which it is usually
incomplete is in its very imperfect
reflective awareness. But the self
may feel itself in danger from the
overall spread of the false-self
system or from one particular
part of it (cf. David's dread of
female impersonation). The
individual in this position is
invariably terrifyingly
'selfconscious ' (see Chapter 7) in
the sense in which this word is
used to mean the exact opposite,
namely, the feeling of being
under observation by the other.
These changes in the relationship
between the different aspects of
the person's relation to himself
are constantly associated with his
inter-personal relationships.
These are complex and never
quite the same from person to
person. The individual's
self-relationship becomes a
pseudo-interpersonal one, and
the self treats the false selves as
though they were other people
whom it depersonalizes. David,
for instance, referring to a part he
played which he found was
disliked, said: 'It had a nasty
tongue.' From within, the self now
looks out at the false things being
said and done and detests the
speaker and doer as though he
were someone else. In all this
there is an attempt to create
relationships to persons and
things within the individual
without recourse to the outer
world of persons and things at
all. The individual is developing a
microcosmos within himself; but,
of course, this autistic, private,
intra-individual 'world' is not a
feasible substitute for the only
world there really is, the shared
The embodied and unembodied
self 75 world. If this were a
feasible project then there would
be no need for psychosis. Such a
schizoid individual in one sense is
trying to be omnipotent by
enclosing within his own being,
without recourse to a creative
relationship with others, modes
of relationship that require the
effective presence to him of other
people and of the outer world. He
would appear to be, in an unreal,
impossible way, all persons and
things to himself. The imagined
advantages are safety for the true
self, isolation and hence freedom
from others, self-sufficiency, and
control. The actual disadvantages
that can be mentioned at this
point are that this project is
impossible and, being a false
hope, leads on to persistent
despair; secondly, a persistent,
haunting sense of futility is the
equally inevitable outcome, since
the hidden shut-up self, in
disowning participation (except,
as David's case, by appearing as
another persona) in the
quasi-autonomous activities of
the falseself systems, is living
only 'mentally'. Moreover, this
shut-up self, being isolated, is
unable to be enriched by outer
experience, and so the whole
inner world comes to be more and
more impoverished, until the
individual may come to feel he is
merely a vacuum. The sense of
being able to do anything and the
feeling of possessing everything
then exist side by side with a
feeling of impotence and
emptiness. The individual who
may at one time have felt
predominantly 'outside' the life
going on there, which he affects
to despise as petty and
commonplace compared to the
richness he has here, inside
himself, now longs to get inside
life again, and get life inside
himself, so dreadful is his inner
deadness. The crucial feature of
the schizoid individual of this type
that we have to understand is the
nature of the anxieties to which
he is subject. We have already
outlined some of the forms these
anxieties take under the terms
engulfment, implosion, and the
dread of losing inner autonomy,
freedom; in short, being turned
from a man with subjectivity to a
thing, a mechanism, a stone, an
it, being petrified. We have yet to
study how these anxieties are
potentiated by the development
of the schizoid organization.
When the self partially abandons
the body and its acts, and
withdraws into mental activity, it
experiences itself as an entity
perhaps localized somewhere in
the body. We have suggested
that 76 The Divided Self this
withdrawal is in part an effort to
preserve its being, since
relationship of any kind with
others is experienced as a threat
to the self's identity. The self feels
safe only in hiding, and isolated.
Such a self can, of course, be
isolated at any time whether
other people are present or not.
But this does not work. No one
feels more 'vulnerable', more
liable to be exposed by the look
of another person than the
schizoid individual. If he is not
acutely aware of being seen by
others ('self-conscious'), he has
temporarily avoided his anxiety
becoming manifest by one or
other of two methods. Either he
turns the other person into a
thing, and depersonalizes or
objectifies his own feelings
towards this thing, or he affects
indifference. The
depersonalization of the person
and/or the attitude of indifference
are closely related but not quite
identical. The depersonalized
person can be used,
manipulated, acted upon. As we
stated above (Chapter 1), the
essential feature of a thing as
opposed to a person is that a
thing has no subjectivity of its
own, and hence can have no
reciprocal intentions. In the
attitude of indifference the person
or thing is treated with
casualness, or callousness, as
though he or it did not matter,
ultimately as though he or it did
not exist. A person minus
subjectivity can still be
important. A thing can still
matter a great deal. Indifference
denies to persons and to things
their significance. Petrification, we
remember, was one of Perseus's
methods of killing his enemies. By
means of the eyes in Medusa's
head, he turned them into
stones. Petrification is one way of
killing. Of course, to feel that
another person is treating or
regarding one not as a person
but as a thing need not itself be
frightening if one is sufficiently
sure of one's own existence.
Thus, being a thing in someone
else's eyes does not represent to
the 'normal' person a catastrophic
threat, but to the schizoid
individual every pair of eyes is in
a Medusa's head which he feels
has power actually to kill or
deaden something precariously
vital in him. He tries therefore to
forestall his own petrification by
turning others into stones. By
doing this he feels he can achieve
some measure of safety.
Generally speaking, the schizoid
individual is not erecting
defences against the loss of a
part of his body. His whole effort
is rather to preserve his self.
This, as we have pointed out, is
pre- The embodied and
unembodied self 77 cariously
established; he is subject to the
dread of his own dissolution into
non-being, into what William
Blake described in the last resort
as 'chaotic non-entity'. His
autonomy is threatened with
engulfment. He has to guard
himself against losing his
subjectivity and sense of being
alive. In so far as he feels empty,
the full, substantial, living reality
of others is an impingement
which is always liable to get out
of hand and become implosive,
threatening to overwhelm and
obliterate his self completely as a
gas will obliterate a vacuum, or as
water will gush in and entirely fill
an empty dam. The schizoid
individual fears a real live
dialectical relationship with real
live people. He can relate himself
only to depersonalized persons,
to phantoms of his own
phantasies (imagos), perhaps to
things, perhaps to animals. We
suggest, therefore, that the
schizoid state we are describing
can be understood as an attempt
to preserve a being that is
precariously structured. We shall
suggest later that the initial
structuralization of being into its
basic elements occurs in early
infancy. In normal circumstances,
this occurs in such a way as to be
so conclusively stable in its basic
elements (for instance, the
continuity of time, the distinction
between the self and not-self,
phantasy and reality), that it can
henceforth be taken for granted:
on this stable base, a
considerable amount of plasticity
can exist in what we call a
person's 'character'. In the
schizoid character structure, on
the other hand, there is an
insecurity in the laying down of
the foundations and a
compensatory rigidity in the
superstructure. If the whole of the
individual's being cannot be
defended, the individual retracts
his lines of defence until he
withdraws within a central
citadel. He is prepared to write off
everything he is, except his 'self'.
But the tragic paradox is that the
more the self is defended in this
way, the more it is destroyed. The
apparent eventual destruction
and dissolution of the self in
schizophrenic conditions is
accomplished not by external
attacks from the enemy (actual
or supposed), from without, but
by the devastation caused by the
inner defensive manoeuvres
themselves. 5 The inner self in
the schizoid condition You can
hold yourself back from the
sufferings of the world, this is
something you are free to do and
is in accord with your nature, but
perhaps precisely this holding
back is the only suffering that you
might be able to avoid. FRANZ
KAFKA In the schizoid condition
here described there is a
persistent scission between the
self and the body. What the
individual regards as his true self
is experienced as more or less
disembodied, and bodily
experience and actions are in turn
felt to be part of the false-self
system. It is now necessary to
consider the two elements in this
split in more detail, and also the
relationship of the one to the
other. First, we consider the
mental or unembodied self. It is
well known that temporary states
of dissociation of the self from the
body occur in normal people. In
general, one can say that it is a
response that appears to be
available to most people who find
themselves enclosed within a
threatening experience from
which there is no physical
escape. Prisoners in concentration
camps tried to feel that way, for
the camp offered no possible way
out either spatially or at the end
of a period of time. The only way
out was by a psychical
withdrawal 'into' one's self and
'out of the body. This dissociation
is characteristically associated
with such thoughts as 'This is like
a dream', 'This seems unreal', 'I
can't believe this is true', 'Nothing
seemed to be touching me', 'I
cannot take it in', 'This is not
happening to me', i.e. with
feelings of estrangement and
derealization. The body may go
on acting in an outwardly normal
way, but inwardly it is felt to be
acting on its own, automatically.
However, despite the
dream-nature or unreality of
experience, and the automatic
nature of action, the self is at the
same time far from 'sleepy';
indeed, it is excessively alert, and
may be thinking and observing
with exceptional lucidity. The
inner self in the schizoid condition
79 The temporary estrangement
of the self from the body may be
represented in dreams. A girl of
nineteen, the date of whose
marriage was fast approaching, a
marriage she had come to dread
for various reasons, dreamed that
she was in the back seat of a car,
which was driving itself. This girl
was not a basically schizoid
person but was reacting by a
schizoid defence to a particular
situation. R. had a dream shortly
before starting treatment. He was
on the footplate of a bus. The bus
had no driver. He jumped off and
the bus went on to crash. One is
tempted to regard a dream he
had after four months of
psychotherapy as a measure of
some change in a desirable
direction. 'I am running after a
bus. Suddenly I'm on the
footplate of the bus, and at the
same time, I'm running after it. I'm
trying to join up with myself on
the bus but I can't entirely catch
up on the bus. I felt frightened at
this.' One could multiply
instances of this common
experience of temporary
dissociation. Sometimes it is
intentionally induced; more
often, it occurs without the
individual's control. But in the
patients here considered, the
splitting is not simply a
temporary reaction to a specific
situation of great danger, which is
reversible when the danger is
past. It is, on the contrary, a basic
orientation to life, and if it is
followed back through their lives
one usually finds that they seem,
in fact, to have emerged from the
early months of infancy with this
split already under way. The
'normal' individual, in a situation
all can see to be threatening to
his being and to offer no real
sense of escape, develops a
schizoid state in trying to get
outside it, if not physically, at
least mentally: he becomes a
mental observer, who looks on,
detached and impassive, at what
his body is doing or what is being
done to his body. If this is so in
the 'normal', it is at least possible
to suppose that the individual
whose abiding mode of
being-in-the-world is of this split
nature is living in what to him, if
not to us, is a world that
threatens his being from all
sides, and from which there is no
exit. This is indeed the case for
such people. For them the world
is a prison without bars, a
concentration camp without
barbed wire. The paranoic has
specific persecutors. Someone is
against him. There is a plot on
foot to steal his brains. A machine
is concealed in the wall of his
bedroom which emits mind rays
to soften his brain, 80 The
Divided Self or to send electric
shocks through him while he is
asleep. The person I am
describing feels at this phase
persecuted by reality itself. The
world as it is, and other people as
they are, are the dangers. The
self then seeks by being
unembodied to transcend the
world and hence to be safe. But a
self is liable to develop which
feels it is outside all experience
and activity. It becomes a
vacuum. Everything is there,
outside; nothing is here, inside.
Moreover, the constant dread of
all that is there, of being
overwhelmed, is potentiated
rather than mitigated by the need
to keep the world at bay. Yet the
self may at the same time long
more than anything for
participation in the world. Thus,
its greatest longing is felt as its
greatest weakness and giving in
to this weakness is its greatest
dread, since in participation the
individual fears that his vacuum
will be obliterated, that he will be
engulfed or otherwise lose his
identity, which has come to be
equated with the maintenance of
the transcendence of the self
even though this is a
transcendence in avoid. This
detachment of the self means
that the self is never revealed
directly in the individual's
expressions and actions, nor does
it experience anything
spontaneously or immediately.
The self's relationship to the
other is always at one remove.
The direct and immediate
transactions between the
individual, the other, and the
world, even in such basic
respects as perceiving and
acting, all come to be
meaningless, futile, and false.
One can represent the alternative
state of affairs schematically as
shown opposite. Objects
perceived by the self are
experienced as real. Thoughts
and feelings of which the self is
the agent are alive and are felt to
have point. Actions to which the
self is committed are felt as
genuine. If the individual
delegates all transactions
between himself and the other to
a system within his being which
is not 'him', then the world is
experienced as unreal, and all
that belongs to this system is felt
to be false, futile, and
meaningless. Everyone is subject
to a certain extent at one time or
another to such moods of futility,
meaninglessness, and
purposelessness, but in schizoid
individuals these moods are
particularly insistent. These
moods arise from the fact that the
doors of perception and/or the 82
The Divided Self gates of action
are not in the command of the
self but are being lived and
operated by a false self. The
unrealness of perceptions and the
falsity and meaninglessness of all
activity are the necessary
consequences of perception and
activity being in the command of
a false self- a system partially
dissociated from the 'true' self,
which is, therefore, excluded from
direct participation in the
individual's relatedness with
other persons and the world. A
pseudo-duality is thus
experienced in the individual's
own being. Instead of the
individual meeting the world with
an integral selfhood, he disavows
part of his own being along' with
his disavowal of immediate
attachment to things and people
in the world. This can be
represented schematically as
follows: Instead of (self/body)
other the situation is self
(body-other) The self, therefore, is
precluded from having a direct
relationship with real things and
real people. When this has
happened in patients, one is
witness to the struggle which
ensues to preserve the self's own
sense of its own realness,
aliveness, and identity. In the
first scheme, one has a benign
circle. The reality of the world and
of the self are mutually
potentiated by the direct
relationship between self and
other. In Figure 2, there is a
vicious circle. Every element in
this diagram comes to be
experienced as more and more
unreal and dead. Love is
precluded and dread takes its
place. The final effect is an
overall experience of everything
having come to a stop. Nothing
moves; nothing is alive;
everything is dead, including the
self. The self by its detachment is
precluded from a full experience
of realness and aliveness. What
one might call a creative
relationship with the other, in
which there is mutual enrichment
of the self and the other (benign
circle), is impossible, and an
interaction is substituted which
may seem to operate efficiently
and smoothly for a while but
which has no 'life' in it (sterile
relationship). There is a quasi-it-it
interaction instead of an I-thou
relationship. This interaction is a
dead process. The inner self
seeks to live by certain
(apparently) compensating
advantages. Such a self cherishes
certain ideals. One, which was
The Divided Self condition called
by Kierkegaard 'shutupness'. The
individual's actions are not felt as
expressions of his self. His
actions, all that David called his
'personality' and which I have
proposed to call his false-self
system, become dissociated and
partly autonomous. The self is
not felt to participate in the
doings of the false self or selves,
and all its or their actions are felt
to be increasingly false and futile.
The self, on the other hand, shut
up with itself, regards itself as the
'true' self and the persona as
false. The individual complains of
futility, of lack of spontaneity, but
he may be cultivating his lack of
spontaneity and thus aggravating
his sense of futility. He says he is
not real and is outside reality and
not properly alive. Existentially,
he is quite right. The self is
extremely aware of itself, and
observes the false self, usually
highly critically. It is characteristic
of the organization of a false self
or persona, on the other hand,
that one way in which it is usually
incomplete is in its very imperfect
reflective awareness. But the self
may feel itself in danger from the
overall spread of the false-self
system or from one particular
part of it (cf. David's dread of
female impersonation). The
individual in this position is
invariably terrifyingly
'selfconscious ' (see Chapter 7) in
the sense in which this word is
used to mean the exact opposite,
namely, the feeling of being
under observation by the other.
These changes in the relationship
between the different aspects of
the person's relation to himself
are constantly associated with his
inter-personal relationships.
These are complex and never
quite the same from person to
person. The individual's
self-relationship becomes a
pseudo-interpersonal one, and
the self treats the false selves as
though they were other people
whom it depersonalizes. David,
for instance, referring to a part he
played which he found was
disliked, said: 'It had a nasty
tongue.' From within, the self now
looks out at the false things being
said and done and detests the
speaker and doer as though he
were someone else. In all this
there is an attempt to create
relationships to persons and
things within the individual
without recourse to the outer
world of persons and things at
all. The individual is developing a
microcosmos within himself; but,
of course, this autistic, private,
intra-individual 'world' is not a
feasible substitute for the only
world there really is, the shared
The embodied and unembodied
self 75 world. If this were a
feasible project then there would
be no need for psychosis. Such a
schizoid individual in one sense is
trying to be omnipotent by
enclosing within his own being,
without recourse to a creative
relationship with others, modes
of relationship that require the
effective presence to him of other
people and of the outer world. He
would appear to be, in an unreal,
impossible way, all persons and
things to himself. The imagined
advantages are safety for the true
self, isolation and hence freedom
from others, self-sufficiency, and
control. The actual disadvantages
that can be mentioned at this
point are that this project is
impossible and, being a false
hope, leads on to persistent
despair; secondly, a persistent,
haunting sense of futility is the
equally inevitable outcome, since
the hidden shut-up self, in
disowning participation (except,
as David's case, by appearing as
another persona) in the
quasi-autonomous activities of
the falseself systems, is living
only 'mentally'. Moreover, this
shut-up self, being isolated, is
unable to be enriched by outer
experience, and so the whole
inner world comes to be more and
more impoverished, until the
individual may come to feel he is
merely a vacuum. The sense of
being able to do anything and the
feeling of possessing everything
then exist side by side with a
feeling of impotence and
emptiness. The individual who
may at one time have felt
predominantly 'outside' the life
going on there, which he affects
to despise as petty and
commonplace compared to the
richness he has here, inside
himself, now longs to get inside
life again, and get life inside
himself, so dreadful is his inner
deadness. The crucial feature of
the schizoid individual of this type
that we have to understand is the
nature of the anxieties to which
he is subject. We have already
outlined some of the forms these
anxieties take under the terms
engulfment, implosion, and the
dread of losing inner autonomy,
freedom; in short, being turned
from a man with subjectivity to a
thing, a mechanism, a stone, an
it, being petrified. We have yet to
study how these anxieties are
potentiated by the development
of the schizoid organization.
When the self partially abandons
the body and its acts, and
withdraws into mental activity, it
experiences itself as an entity
perhaps localized somewhere in
the body. We have suggested
that 76 The Divided Self this
withdrawal is in part an effort to
preserve its being, since
relationship of any kind with
others is experienced as a threat
to the self's identity. The self feels
safe only in hiding, and isolated.
Such a self can, of course, be
isolated at any time whether
other people are present or not.
But this does not work. No one
feels more 'vulnerable', more
liable to be exposed by the look
of another person than the
schizoid individual. If he is not
acutely aware of being seen by
others ('self-conscious'), he has
temporarily avoided his anxiety
becoming manifest by one or
other of two methods. Either he
turns the other person into a
thing, and depersonalizes or
objectifies his own feelings
towards this thing, or he affects
indifference. The
depersonalization of the person
and/or the attitude of indifference
are closely related but not quite
identical. The depersonalized
person can be used,
manipulated, acted upon. As we
stated above (Chapter 1), the
essential feature of a thing as
opposed to a person is that a
thing has no subjectivity of its
own, and hence can have no
reciprocal intentions. In the
attitude of indifference the person
or thing is treated with
casualness, or callousness, as
though he or it did not matter,
ultimately as though he or it did
not exist. A person minus
subjectivity can still be
important. A thing can still
matter a great deal. Indifference
denies to persons and to things
their significance. Petrification, we
remember, was one of Perseus's
methods of killing his enemies. By
means of the eyes in Medusa's
head, he turned them into
stones. Petrification is one way of
killing. Of course, to feel that
another person is treating or
regarding one not as a person
but as a thing need not itself be
frightening if one is sufficiently
sure of one's own existence.
Thus, being a thing in someone
else's eyes does not represent to
the 'normal' person a catastrophic
threat, but to the schizoid
individual every pair of eyes is in
a Medusa's head which he feels
has power actually to kill or
deaden something precariously
vital in him. He tries therefore to
forestall his own petrification by
turning others into stones. By
doing this he feels he can achieve
some measure of safety.
Generally speaking, the schizoid
individual is not erecting
defences against the loss of a
part of his body. His whole effort
is rather to preserve his self.
This, as we have pointed out, is
pre- The embodied and
unembodied self 77 cariously
established; he is subject to the
dread of his own dissolution into
non-being, into what William
Blake described in the last resort
as 'chaotic non-entity'. His
autonomy is threatened with
engulfment. He has to guard
himself against losing his
subjectivity and sense of being
alive. In so far as he feels empty,
the full, substantial, living reality
of others is an impingement
which is always liable to get out
of hand and become implosive,
threatening to overwhelm and
obliterate his self completely as a
gas will obliterate a vacuum, or as
water will gush in and entirely fill
an empty dam. The schizoid
individual fears a real live
dialectical relationship with real
live people. He can relate himself
only to depersonalized persons,
to phantoms of his own
phantasies (imagos), perhaps to
things, perhaps to animals. We
suggest, therefore, that the
schizoid state we are describing
can be understood as an attempt
to preserve a being that is
precariously structured. We shall
suggest later that the initial
structuralization of being into its
basic elements occurs in early
infancy. In normal circumstances,
this occurs in such a way as to be
so conclusively stable in its basic
elements (for instance, the
continuity of time, the distinction
between the self and not-self,
phantasy and reality), that it can
henceforth be taken for granted:
on this stable base, a
considerable amount of plasticity
can exist in what we call a
person's 'character'. In the
schizoid character structure, on
the other hand, there is an
insecurity in the laying down of
the foundations and a
compensatory rigidity in the
superstructure. If the whole of the
individual's being cannot be
defended, the individual retracts
his lines of defence until he
withdraws within a central
citadel. He is prepared to write off
everything he is, except his 'self'.
But the tragic paradox is that the
more the self is defended in this
way, the more it is destroyed. The
apparent eventual destruction
and dissolution of the self in
schizophrenic conditions is
accomplished not by external
attacks from the enemy (actual
or supposed), from without, but
by the devastation caused by the
inner defensive manoeuvres
themselves. 5 The inner self in
the schizoid condition You can
hold yourself back from the
sufferings of the world, this is
something you are free to do and
is in accord with your nature, but
perhaps precisely this holding
back is the only suffering that you
might be able to avoid. FRANZ
KAFKA In the schizoid condition
here described there is a
persistent scission between the
self and the body. What the
individual regards as his true self
is experienced as more or less
disembodied, and bodily
experience and actions are in turn
felt to be part of the false-self
system. It is now necessary to
consider the two elements in this
split in more detail, and also the
relationship of the one to the
other. First, we consider the
mental or unembodied self. It is
well known that temporary states
of dissociation of the self from the
body occur in normal people. In
general, one can say that it is a
response that appears to be
available to most people who find
themselves enclosed within a
threatening experience from
which there is no physical
escape. Prisoners in concentration
camps tried to feel that way, for
the camp offered no possible way
out either spatially or at the end
of a period of time. The only way
out was by a psychical
withdrawal 'into' one's self and
'out of the body. This dissociation
is characteristically associated
with such thoughts as 'This is like
a dream', 'This seems unreal', 'I
can't believe this is true', 'Nothing
seemed to be touching me', 'I
cannot take it in', 'This is not
happening to me', i.e. with
feelings of estrangement and
derealization. The body may go
on acting in an outwardly normal
way, but inwardly it is felt to be
acting on its own, automatically.
However, despite the
dream-nature or unreality of
experience, and the automatic
nature of action, the self is at the
same time far from 'sleepy';
indeed, it is excessively alert, and
may be thinking and observing
with exceptional lucidity. The
inner self in the schizoid condition
79 The temporary estrangement
of the self from the body may be
represented in dreams. A girl of
nineteen, the date of whose
marriage was fast approaching, a
marriage she had come to dread
for various reasons, dreamed that
she was in the back seat of a car,
which was driving itself. This girl
was not a basically schizoid
person but was reacting by a
schizoid defence to a particular
situation. R. had a dream shortly
before starting treatment. He was
on the footplate of a bus. The bus
had no driver. He jumped off and
the bus went on to crash. One is
tempted to regard a dream he
had after four months of
psychotherapy as a measure of
some change in a desirable
direction. 'I am running after a
bus. Suddenly I'm on the
footplate of the bus, and at the
same time, I'm running after it. I'm
trying to join up with myself on
the bus but I can't entirely catch
up on the bus. I felt frightened at
this.' One could multiply
instances of this common
experience of temporary
dissociation. Sometimes it is
intentionally induced; more
often, it occurs without the
individual's control. But in the
patients here considered, the
splitting is not simply a
temporary reaction to a specific
situation of great danger, which is
reversible when the danger is
past. It is, on the contrary, a basic
orientation to life, and if it is
followed back through their lives
one usually finds that they seem,
in fact, to have emerged from the
early months of infancy with this
split already under way. The
'normal' individual, in a situation
all can see to be threatening to
his being and to offer no real
sense of escape, develops a
schizoid state in trying to get
outside it, if not physically, at
least mentally: he becomes a
mental observer, who looks on,
detached and impassive, at what
his body is doing or what is being
done to his body. If this is so in
the 'normal', it is at least possible
to suppose that the individual
whose abiding mode of
being-in-the-world is of this split
nature is living in what to him, if
not to us, is a world that
threatens his being from all
sides, and from which there is no
exit. This is indeed the case for
such people. For them the world
is a prison without bars, a
concentration camp without
barbed wire. The paranoic has
specific persecutors. Someone is
against him. There is a plot on
foot to steal his brains. A machine
is concealed in the wall of his
bedroom which emits mind rays
to soften his brain, 80 The
Divided Self or to send electric
shocks through him while he is
asleep. The person I am
describing feels at this phase
persecuted by reality itself. The
world as it is, and other people as
they are, are the dangers. The
self then seeks by being
unembodied to transcend the
world and hence to be safe. But a
self is liable to develop which
feels it is outside all experience
and activity. It becomes a
vacuum. Everything is there,
outside; nothing is here, inside.
Moreover, the constant dread of
all that is there, of being
overwhelmed, is potentiated
rather than mitigated by the need
to keep the world at bay. Yet the
self may at the same time long
more than anything for
participation in the world. Thus,
its greatest longing is felt as its
greatest weakness and giving in
to this weakness is its greatest
dread, since in participation the
individual fears that his vacuum
will be obliterated, that he will be
engulfed or otherwise lose his
identity, which has come to be
equated with the maintenance of
the transcendence of the self
even though this is a
transcendence in avoid. This
detachment of the self means
that the self is never revealed
directly in the individual's
expressions and actions, nor does
it experience anything
spontaneously or immediately.
The self's relationship to the
other is always at one remove.
The direct and immediate
transactions between the
individual, the other, and the
world, even in such basic
respects as perceiving and
acting, all come to be
meaningless, futile, and false.
One can represent the alternative
state of affairs schematically as
shown opposite. Objects
perceived by the self are
experienced as real. Thoughts
and feelings of which the self is
the agent are alive and are felt to
have point. Actions to which the
self is committed are felt as
genuine. If the individual
delegates all transactions
between himself and the other to
a system within his being which
is not 'him', then the world is
experienced as unreal, and all
that belongs to this system is felt
to be false, futile, and
meaningless. Everyone is subject
to a certain extent at one time or
another to such moods of futility,
meaninglessness, and
purposelessness, but in schizoid
individuals these moods are
particularly insistent. These
moods arise from the fact that the
doors of perception and/or the 82
The Divided Self gates of action
are not in the command of the
self but are being lived and
operated by a false self. The
unrealness of perceptions and the
falsity and meaninglessness of all
activity are the necessary
consequences of perception and
activity being in the command of
a false self- a system partially
dissociated from the 'true' self,
which is, therefore, excluded from
direct participation in the
individual's relatedness with
other persons and the world. A
pseudo-duality is thus
experienced in the individual's
own being. Instead of the
individual meeting the world with
an integral selfhood, he disavows
part of his own being along' with
his disavowal of immediate
attachment to things and people
in the world. This can be
represented schematically as
follows: Instead of (self/body)
other the situation is self
(body-other) The self, therefore, is
precluded from having a direct
relationship with real things and
real people. When this has
happened in patients, one is
witness to the struggle which
ensues to preserve the self's own
sense of its own realness,
aliveness, and identity. In the
first scheme, one has a benign
circle. The reality of the world and
of the self are mutually
potentiated by the direct
relationship between self and
other. In Figure 2, there is a
vicious circle. Every element in
this diagram comes to be
experienced as more and more
unreal and dead. Love is
precluded and dread takes its
place. The final effect is an
overall experience of everything
having come to a stop. Nothing
moves; nothing is alive;
everything is dead, including the
self. The self by its detachment is
precluded from a full experience
of realness and aliveness. What
one might call a creative
relationship with the other, in
which there is mutual enrichment
of the self and the other (benign
circle), is impossible, and an
interaction is substituted which
may seem to operate efficiently
and smoothly for a while but
which has no 'life' in it (sterile
relationship). There is a quasi-it-it
interaction instead of an I-thou
relationship. This interaction is a
dead process. The inner self
seeks to live by certain
(apparently) compensating
advantages. Such a self cherishes
certain ideals. One, which wasThe
Divided Self condition called by
Kierkegaard 'shutupness'. The
individual's actions are not felt as
expressions of his self. His
actions, all that David called his
'personality' and which I have
proposed to call his false-self
system, become dissociated and
partly autonomous. The self is
not felt to participate in the
doings of the false self or selves,
and all its or their actions are felt
to be increasingly false and futile.
The self, on the other hand, shut
up with itself, regards itself as the
'true' self and the persona as
false. The individual complains of
futility, of lack of spontaneity, but
he may be cultivating his lack of
spontaneity and thus aggravating
his sense of futility. He says he is
not real and is outside reality and
not properly alive. Existentially,
he is quite right. The self is
extremely aware of itself, and
observes the false self, usually
highly critically. It is characteristic
of the organization of a false self
or persona, on the other hand,
that one way in which it is usually
incomplete is in its very imperfect
reflective awareness. But the self
may feel itself in danger from the
overall spread of the false-self
system or from one particular
part of it (cf. David's dread of
female impersonation). The
individual in this position is
invariably terrifyingly
'selfconscious ' (see Chapter 7) in
the sense in which this word is
used to mean the exact opposite,
namely, the feeling of being
under observation by the other.
These changes in the relationship
between the different aspects of
the person's relation to himself
are constantly associated with his
inter-personal relationships.
These are complex and never
quite the same from person to
person. The individual's
self-relationship becomes a
pseudo-interpersonal one, and
the self treats the false selves as
though they were other people
whom it depersonalizes. David,
for instance, referring to a part he
played which he found was
disliked, said: 'It had a nasty
tongue.' From within, the self now
looks out at the false things being
said and done and detests the
speaker and doer as though he
were someone else. In all this
there is an attempt to create
relationships to persons and
things within the individual
without recourse to the outer
world of persons and things at
all. The individual is developing a
microcosmos within himself; but,
of course, this autistic, private,
intra-individual 'world' is not a
feasible substitute for the only
world there really is, the shared
The embodied and unembodied
self 75 world. If this were a
feasible project then there would
be no need for psychosis. Such a
schizoid individual in one sense is
trying to be omnipotent by
enclosing within his own being,
without recourse to a creative
relationship with others, modes
of relationship that require the
effective presence to him of other
people and of the outer world. He
would appear to be, in an unreal,
impossible way, all persons and
things to himself. The imagined
advantages are safety for the true
self, isolation and hence freedom
from others, self-sufficiency, and
control. The actual disadvantages
that can be mentioned at this
point are that this project is
impossible and, being a false
hope, leads on to persistent
despair; secondly, a persistent,
haunting sense of futility is the
equally inevitable outcome, since
the hidden shut-up self, in
disowning participation (except,
as David's case, by appearing as
another persona) in the
quasi-autonomous activities of
the falseself systems, is living
only 'mentally'. Moreover, this
shut-up self, being isolated, is
unable to be enriched by outer
experience, and so the whole
inner world comes to be more and
more impoverished, until the
individual may come to feel he is
merely a vacuum. The sense of
being able to do anything and the
feeling of possessing everything
then exist side by side with a
feeling of impotence and
emptiness. The individual who
may at one time have felt
predominantly 'outside' the life
going on there, which he affects
to despise as petty and
commonplace compared to the
richness he has here, inside
himself, now longs to get inside
life again, and get life inside
himself, so dreadful is his inner
deadness. The crucial feature of
the schizoid individual of this type
that we have to understand is the
nature of the anxieties to which
he is subject. We have already
outlined some of the forms these
anxieties take under the terms
engulfment, implosion, and the
dread of losing inner autonomy,
freedom; in short, being turned
from a man with subjectivity to a
thing, a mechanism, a stone, an
it, being petrified. We have yet to
study how these anxieties are
potentiated by the development
of the schizoid organization.
When the self partially abandons
the body and its acts, and
withdraws into mental activity, it
experiences itself as an entity
perhaps localized somewhere in
the body. We have suggested
that 76 The Divided Self this
withdrawal is in part an effort to
preserve its being, since
relationship of any kind with
others is experienced as a threat
to the self's identity. The self feels
safe only in hiding, and isolated.
Such a self can, of course, be
isolated at any time whether
other people are present or not.
But this does not work. No one
feels more 'vulnerable', more
liable to be exposed by the look
of another person than the
schizoid individual. If he is not
acutely aware of being seen by
others ('self-conscious'), he has
temporarily avoided his anxiety
becoming manifest by one or
other of two methods. Either he
turns the other person into a
thing, and depersonalizes or
objectifies his own feelings
towards this thing, or he affects
indifference. The
depersonalization of the person
and/or the attitude of indifference
are closely related but not quite
identical. The depersonalized
person can be used,
manipulated, acted upon. As we
stated above (Chapter 1), the
essential feature of a thing as
opposed to a person is that a
thing has no subjectivity of its
own, and hence can have no
reciprocal intentions. In the
attitude of indifference the person
or thing is treated with
casualness, or callousness, as
though he or it did not matter,
ultimately as though he or it did
not exist. A person minus
subjectivity can still be
important. A thing can still
matter a great deal. Indifference
denies to persons and to things
their significance. Petrification, we
remember, was one of Perseus's
methods of killing his enemies. By
means of the eyes in Medusa's
head, he turned them into
stones. Petrification is one way of
killing. Of course, to feel that
another person is treating or
regarding one not as a person
but as a thing need not itself be
frightening if one is sufficiently
sure of one's own existence.
Thus, being a thing in someone
else's eyes does not represent to
the 'normal' person a catastrophic
threat, but to the schizoid
individual every pair of eyes is in
a Medusa's head which he feels
has power actually to kill or
deaden something precariously
vital in him. He tries therefore to
forestall his own petrification by
turning others into stones. By
doing this he feels he can achieve
some measure of safety.
Generally speaking, the schizoid
individual is not erecting
defences against the loss of a
part of his body. His whole effort
is rather to preserve his self.
This, as we have pointed out, is
pre- The embodied and
unembodied self 77 cariously
established; he is subject to the
dread of his own dissolution into
non-being, into what William
Blake described in the last resort
as 'chaotic non-entity'. His
autonomy is threatened with
engulfment. He has to guard
himself against losing his
subjectivity and sense of being
alive. In so far as he feels empty,
the full, substantial, living reality
of others is an impingement
which is always liable to get out
of hand and become implosive,
threatening to overwhelm and
obliterate his self completely as a
gas will obliterate a vacuum, or as
water will gush in and entirely fill
an empty dam. The schizoid
individual fears a real live
dialectical relationship with real
live people. He can relate himself
only to depersonalized persons,
to phantoms of his own
phantasies (imagos), perhaps to
things, perhaps to animals. We
suggest, therefore, that the
schizoid state we are describing
can be understood as an attempt
to preserve a being that is
precariously structured. We shall
suggest later that the initial
structuralization of being into its
basic elements occurs in early
infancy. In normal circumstances,
this occurs in such a way as to be
so conclusively stable in its basic
elements (for instance, the
continuity of time, the distinction
between the self and not-self,
phantasy and reality), that it can
henceforth be taken for granted:
on this stable base, a
considerable amount of plasticity
can exist in what we call a
person's 'character'. In the
schizoid character structure, on
the other hand, there is an
insecurity in the laying down of
the foundations and a
compensatory rigidity in the
superstructure. If the whole of the
individual's being cannot be
defended, the individual retracts
his lines of defence until he
withdraws within a central
citadel. He is prepared to write off
everything he is, except his 'self'.
But the tragic paradox is that the
more the self is defended in this
way, the more it is destroyed. The
apparent eventual destruction
and dissolution of the self in
schizophrenic conditions is
accomplished not by external
attacks from the enemy (actual
or supposed), from without, but
by the devastation caused by the
inner defensive manoeuvres
themselves. 5 The inner self in
the schizoid condition You can
hold yourself back from the
sufferings of the world, this is
something you are free to do and
is in accord with your nature, but
perhaps precisely this holding
back is the only suffering that you
might be able to avoid. FRANZ
KAFKA In the schizoid condition
here described there is a
persistent scission between the
self and the body. What the
individual regards as his true self
is experienced as more or less
disembodied, and bodily
experience and actions are in turn
felt to be part of the false-self
system. It is now necessary to
consider the two elements in this
split in more detail, and also the
relationship of the one to the
other. First, we consider the
mental or unembodied self. It is
well known that temporary states
of dissociation of the self from the
body occur in normal people. In
general, one can say that it is a
response that appears to be
available to most people who find
themselves enclosed within a
threatening experience from
which there is no physical
escape. Prisoners in concentration
camps tried to feel that way, for
the camp offered no possible way
out either spatially or at the end
of a period of time. The only way
out was by a psychical
withdrawal 'into' one's self and
'out of the body. This dissociation
is characteristically associated
with such thoughts as 'This is like
a dream', 'This seems unreal', 'I
can't believe this is true', 'Nothing
seemed to be touching me', 'I
cannot take it in', 'This is not
happening to me', i.e. with
feelings of estrangement and
derealization. The body may go
on acting in an outwardly normal
way, but inwardly it is felt to be
acting on its own, automatically.
However, despite the
dream-nature or unreality of
experience, and the automatic
nature of action, the self is at the
same time far from 'sleepy';
indeed, it is excessively alert, and
may be thinking and observing
with exceptional lucidity. The
inner self in the schizoid condition
79 The temporary estrangement
of the self from the body may be
represented in dreams. A girl of
nineteen, the date of whose
marriage was fast approaching, a
marriage she had come to dread
for various reasons, dreamed that
she was in the back seat of a car,
which was driving itself. This girl
was not a basically schizoid
person but was reacting by a
schizoid defence to a particular
situation. R. had a dream shortly
before starting treatment. He was
on the footplate of a bus. The bus
had no driver. He jumped off and
the bus went on to crash. One is
tempted to regard a dream he
had after four months of
psychotherapy as a measure of
some change in a desirable
direction. 'I am running after a
bus. Suddenly I'm on the
footplate of the bus, and at the
same time, I'm running after it. I'm
trying to join up with myself on
the bus but I can't entirely catch
up on the bus. I felt frightened at
this.' One could multiply
instances of this common
experience of temporary
dissociation. Sometimes it is
intentionally induced; more
often, it occurs without the
individual's control. But in the
patients here considered, the
splitting is not simply a
temporary reaction to a specific
situation of great danger, which is
reversible when the danger is
past. It is, on the contrary, a basic
orientation to life, and if it is
followed back through their lives
one usually finds that they seem,
in fact, to have emerged from the
early months of infancy with this
split already under way. The
'normal' individual, in a situation
all can see to be threatening to
his being and to offer no real
sense of escape, develops a
schizoid state in trying to get
outside it, if not physically, at
least mentally: he becomes a
mental observer, who looks on,
detached and impassive, at what
his body is doing or what is being
done to his body. If this is so in
the 'normal', it is at least possible
to suppose that the individual
whose abiding mode of
being-in-the-world is of this split
nature is living in what to him, if
not to us, is a world that
threatens his being from all
sides, and from which there is no
exit. This is indeed the case for
such people. For them the world
is a prison without bars, a
concentration camp without
barbed wire. The paranoic has
specific persecutors. Someone is
against him. There is a plot on
foot to steal his brains. A machine
is concealed in the wall of his
bedroom which emits mind rays
to soften his brain, 80 The
Divided Self or to send electric
shocks through him while he is
asleep. The person I am
describing feels at this phase
persecuted by reality itself. The
world as it is, and other people as
they are, are the dangers. The
self then seeks by being
unembodied to transcend the
world and hence to be safe. But a
self is liable to develop which
feels it is outside all experience
and activity. It becomes a
vacuum. Everything is there,
outside; nothing is here, inside.
Moreover, the constant dread of
all that is there, of being
overwhelmed, is potentiated
rather than mitigated by the need
to keep the world at bay. Yet the
self may at the same time long
more than anything for
participation in the world. Thus,
its greatest longing is felt as its
greatest weakness and giving in
to this weakness is its greatest
dread, since in participation the
individual fears that his vacuum
will be obliterated, that he will be
engulfed or otherwise lose his
identity, which has come to be
equated with the maintenance of
the transcendence of the self
even though this is a
transcendence in avoid. This
detachment of the self means
that the self is never revealed
directly in the individual's
expressions and actions, nor does
it experience anything
spontaneously or immediately.
The self's relationship to the
other is always at one remove.
The direct and immediate
transactions between the
individual, the other, and the
world, even in such basic
respects as perceiving and
acting, all come to be
meaningless, futile, and false.
One can represent the alternative
state of affairs schematically as
shown opposite. Objects
perceived by the self are
experienced as real. Thoughts
and feelings of which the self is
the agent are alive and are felt to
have point. Actions to which the
self is committed are felt as
genuine. If the individual
delegates all transactions
between himself and the other to
a system within his being which
is not 'him', then the world is
experienced as unreal, and all
that belongs to this system is felt
to be false, futile, and
meaningless. Everyone is subject
to a certain extent at one time or
another to such moods of futility,
meaninglessness, and
purposelessness, but in schizoid
individuals these moods are
particularly insistent. These
moods arise from the fact that the
doors of perception and/or the 82
The Divided Self gates of action
are not in the command of the
self but are being lived and
operated by a false self. The
unrealness of perceptions and the
falsity and meaninglessness of all
activity are the necessary
consequences of perception and
activity being in the command of
a false self- a system partially
dissociated from the 'true' self,
which is, therefore, excluded from
direct participation in the
individual's relatedness with
other persons and the world. A
pseudo-duality is thus
experienced in the individual's
own being. Instead of the
individual meeting the world with
an integral selfhood, he disavows
part of his own being along' with
his disavowal of immediate
attachment to things and people
in the world. This can be
represented schematically as
follows: Instead of (self/body)
other the situation is self
(body-other) The self, therefore, is
precluded from having a direct
relationship with real things and
real people. When this has
happened in patients, one is
witness to the struggle which
ensues to preserve the self's own
sense of its own realness,
aliveness, and identity. In the
first scheme, one has a benign
circle. The reality of the world and
of the self are mutually
potentiated by the direct
relationship between self and
other. In Figure 2, there is a
vicious circle. Every element in
this diagram comes to be
experienced as more and more
unreal and dead. Love is
precluded and dread takes its
place. The final effect is an
overall experience of everything
having come to a stop. Nothing
moves; nothing is alive;
everything is dead, including the
self. The self by its detachment is
precluded from a full experience
of realness and aliveness. What
one might call a creative
relationship with the other, in
which there is mutual enrichment
of the self and the other (benign
circle), is impossible, and an
interaction is substituted which
may seem to operate efficiently
and smoothly for a while but
which has no 'life' in it (sterile
relationship). There is a quasi-it-it
interaction instead of an I-thou
relationship. This interaction is a
dead process. The inner self
seeks to live by certain
(apparently) compensating
advantages. Such a self cherishes
certain ideals. One, which wasThe
Divided Self condition called by
Kierkegaard 'shutupness'. The
individual's actions are not felt as
expressions of his self. His
actions, all that David called his
'personality' and which I have
proposed to call his false-self
system, become dissociated and
partly autonomous. The self is
not felt to participate in the
doings of the false self or selves,
and all its or their actions are felt
to be increasingly false and futile.
The self, on the other hand, shut
up with itself, regards itself as the
'true' self and the persona as
false. The individual complains of
futility, of lack of spontaneity, but
he may be cultivating his lack of
spontaneity and thus aggravating
his sense of futility. He says he is
not real and is outside reality and
not properly alive. Existentially,
he is quite right. The self is
extremely aware of itself, and
observes the false self, usually
highly critically. It is characteristic
of the organization of a false self
or persona, on the other hand,
that one way in which it is usually
incomplete is in its very imperfect
reflective awareness. But the self
may feel itself in danger from the
overall spread of the false-self
system or from one particular
part of it (cf. David's dread of
female impersonation). The
individual in this position is
invariably terrifyingly
'selfconscious ' (see Chapter 7) in
the sense in which this word is
used to mean the exact opposite,
namely, the feeling of being
under observation by the other.
These changes in the relationship
between the different aspects of
the person's relation to himself
are constantly associated with his
inter-personal relationships.
These are complex and never
quite the same from person to
person. The individual's
self-relationship becomes a
pseudo-interpersonal one, and
the self treats the false selves as
though they were other people
whom it depersonalizes. David,
for instance, referring to a part he
played which he found was
disliked, said: 'It had a nasty
tongue.' From within, the self now
looks out at the false things being
said and done and detests the
speaker and doer as though he
were someone else. In all this
there is an attempt to create
relationships to persons and
things within the individual
without recourse to the outer
world of persons and things at
all. The individual is developing a
microcosmos within himself; but,
of course, this autistic, private,
intra-individual 'world' is not a
feasible substitute for the only
world there really is, the shared
The embodied and unembodied
self 75 world. If this were a
feasible project then there would
be no need for psychosis. Such a
schizoid individual in one sense is
trying to be omnipotent by
enclosing within his own being,
without recourse to a creative
relationship with others, modes
of relationship that require the
effective presence to him of other
people and of the outer world. He
would appear to be, in an unreal,
impossible way, all persons and
things to himself. The imagined
advantages are safety for the true
self, isolation and hence freedom
from others, self-sufficiency, and
control. The actual disadvantages
that can be mentioned at this
point are that this project is
impossible and, being a false
hope, leads on to persistent
despair; secondly, a persistent,
haunting sense of futility is the
equally inevitable outcome, since
the hidden shut-up self, in
disowning participation (except,
as David's case, by appearing as
another persona) in the
quasi-autonomous activities of
the falseself systems, is living
only 'mentally'. Moreover, this
shut-up self, being isolated, is
unable to be enriched by outer
experience, and so the whole
inner world comes to be more and
more impoverished, until the
individual may come to feel he is
merely a vacuum. The sense of
being able to do anything and the
feeling of possessing everything
then exist side by side with a
feeling of impotence and
emptiness. The individual who
may at one time have felt
predominantly 'outside' the life
going on there, which he affects
to despise as petty and
commonplace compared to the
richness he has here, inside
himself, now longs to get inside
life again, and get life inside
himself, so dreadful is his inner
deadness. The crucial feature of
the schizoid individual of this type
that we have to understand is the
nature of the anxieties to which
he is subject. We have already
outlined some of the forms these
anxieties take under the terms
engulfment, implosion, and the
dread of losing inner autonomy,
freedom; in short, being turned
from a man with subjectivity to a
thing, a mechanism, a stone, an
it, being petrified. We have yet to
study how these anxieties are
potentiated by the development
of the schizoid organization.
When the self partially abandons
the body and its acts, and
withdraws into mental activity, it
experiences itself as an entity
perhaps localized somewhere in
the body. We have suggested
that 76 The Divided Self this
withdrawal is in part an effort to
preserve its being, since
relationship of any kind with
others is experienced as a threat
to the self's identity. The self feels
safe only in hiding, and isolated.
Such a self can, of course, be
isolated at any time whether
other people are present or not.
But this does not work. No one
feels more 'vulnerable', more
liable to be exposed by the look
of another person than the
schizoid individual. If he is not
acutely aware of being seen by
others ('self-conscious'), he has
temporarily avoided his anxiety
becoming manifest by one or
other of two methods. Either he
turns the other person into a
thing, and depersonalizes or
objectifies his own feelings
towards this thing, or he affects
indifference. The
depersonalization of the person
and/or the attitude of indifference
are closely related but not quite
identical. The depersonalized
person can be used,
manipulated, acted upon. As we
stated above (Chapter 1), the
essential feature of a thing as
opposed to a person is that a
thing has no subjectivity of its
own, and hence can have no
reciprocal intentions. In the
attitude of indifference the person
or thing is treated with
casualness, or callousness, as
though he or it did not matter,
ultimately as though he or it did
not exist. A person minus
subjectivity can still be
important. A thing can still
matter a great deal. Indifference
denies to persons and to things
their significance. Petrification, we
remember, was one of Perseus's
methods of killing his enemies. By
means of the eyes in Medusa's
head, he turned them into
stones. Petrification is one way of
killing. Of course, to feel that
another person is treating or
regarding one not as a person
but as a thing need not itself be
frightening if one is sufficiently
sure of one's own existence.
Thus, being a thing in someone
else's eyes does not represent to
the 'normal' person a catastrophic
threat, but to the schizoid
individual every pair of eyes is in
a Medusa's head which he feels
has power actually to kill or
deaden something precariously
vital in him. He tries therefore to
forestall his own petrification by
turning others into stones. By
doing this he feels he can achieve
some measure of safety.
Generally speaking, the schizoid
individual is not erecting
defences against the loss of a
part of his body. His whole effort
is rather to preserve his self.
This, as we have pointed out, is
pre- The embodied and
unembodied self 77 cariously
established; he is subject to the
dread of his own dissolution into
non-being, into what William
Blake described in the last resort
as 'chaotic non-entity'. His
autonomy is threatened with
engulfment. He has to guard
himself against losing his
subjectivity and sense of being
alive. In so far as he feels empty,
the full, substantial, living reality
of others is an impingement
which is always liable to get out
of hand and become implosive,
threatening to overwhelm and
obliterate his self completely as a
gas will obliterate a vacuum, or as
water will gush in and entirely fill
an empty dam. The schizoid
individual fears a real live
dialectical relationship with real
live people. He can relate himself
only to depersonalized persons,
to phantoms of his own
phantasies (imagos), perhaps to
things, perhaps to animals. We
suggest, therefore, that the
schizoid state we are describing
can be understood as an attempt
to preserve a being that is
precariously structured. We shall
suggest later that the initial
structuralization of being into its
basic elements occurs in early
infancy. In normal circumstances,
this occurs in such a way as to be
so conclusively stable in its basic
elements (for instance, the
continuity of time, the distinction
between the self and not-self,
phantasy and reality), that it can
henceforth be taken for granted:
on this stable base, a
considerable amount of plasticity
can exist in what we call a
person's 'character'. In the
schizoid character structure, on
the other hand, there is an
insecurity in the laying down of
the foundations and a
compensatory rigidity in the
superstructure. If the whole of the
individual's being cannot be
defended, the individual retracts
his lines of defence until he
withdraws within a central
citadel. He is prepared to write off
everything he is, except his 'self'.
But the tragic paradox is that the
more the self is defended in this
way, the more it is destroyed. The
apparent eventual destruction
and dissolution of the self in
schizophrenic conditions is
accomplished not by external
attacks from the enemy (actual
or supposed), from without, but
by the devastation caused by the
inner defensive manoeuvres
themselves. 5 The inner self in
the schizoid condition You can
hold yourself back from the
sufferings of the world, this is
something you are free to do and
is in accord with your nature, but
perhaps precisely this holding
back is the only suffering that you
might be able to avoid. FRANZ
KAFKA In the schizoid condition
here described there is a
persistent scission between the
self and the body. What the
individual regards as his true self
is experienced as more or less
disembodied, and bodily
experience and actions are in turn
felt to be part of the false-self
system. It is now necessary to
consider the two elements in this
split in more detail, and also the
relationship of the one to the
other. First, we consider the
mental or unembodied self. It is
well known that temporary states
of dissociation of the self from the
body occur in normal people. In
general, one can say that it is a
response that appears to be
available to most people who find
themselves enclosed within a
threatening experience from
which there is no physical
escape. Prisoners in concentration
camps tried to feel that way, for
the camp offered no possible way
out either spatially or at the end
of a period of time. The only way
out was by a psychical
withdrawal 'into' one's self and
'out of the body. This dissociation
is characteristically associated
with such thoughts as 'This is like
a dream', 'This seems unreal', 'I
can't believe this is true', 'Nothing
seemed to be touching me', 'I
cannot take it in', 'This is not
happening to me', i.e. with
feelings of estrangement and
derealization. The body may go
on acting in an outwardly normal
way, but inwardly it is felt to be
acting on its own, automatically.
However, despite the
dream-nature or unreality of
experience, and the automatic
nature of action, the self is at the
same time far from 'sleepy';
indeed, it is excessively alert, and
may be thinking and observing
with exceptional lucidity. The
inner self in the schizoid condition
79 The temporary estrangement
of the self from the body may be
represented in dreams. A girl of
nineteen, the date of whose
marriage was fast approaching, a
marriage she had come to dread
for various reasons, dreamed that
she was in the back seat of a car,
which was driving itself. This girl
was not a basically schizoid
person but was reacting by a
schizoid defence to a particular
situation. R. had a dream shortly
before starting treatment. He was
on the footplate of a bus. The bus
had no driver. He jumped off and
the bus went on to crash. One is
tempted to regard a dream he
had after four months of
psychotherapy as a measure of
some change in a desirable
direction. 'I am running after a
bus. Suddenly I'm on the
footplate of the bus, and at the
same time, I'm running after it. I'm
trying to join up with myself on
the bus but I can't entirely catch
up on the bus. I felt frightened at
this.' One could multiply
instances of this common
experience of temporary
dissociation. Sometimes it is
intentionally induced; more
often, it occurs without the
individual's control. But in the
patients here considered, the
splitting is not simply a
temporary reaction to a specific
situation of great danger, which is
reversible when the danger is
past. It is, on the contrary, a basic
orientation to life, and if it is
followed back through their lives
one usually finds that they seem,
in fact, to have emerged from the
early months of infancy with this
split already under way. The
'normal' individual, in a situation
all can see to be threatening to
his being and to offer no real
sense of escape, develops a
schizoid state in trying to get
outside it, if not physically, at
least mentally: he becomes a
mental observer, who looks on,
detached and impassive, at what
his body is doing or what is being
done to his body. If this is so in
the 'normal', it is at least possible
to suppose that the individual
whose abiding mode of
being-in-the-world is of this split
nature is living in what to him, if
not to us, is a world that
threatens his being from all
sides, and from which there is no
exit. This is indeed the case for
such people. For them the world
is a prison without bars, a
concentration camp without
barbed wire. The paranoic has
specific persecutors. Someone is
against him. There is a plot on
foot to steal his brains. A machine
is concealed in the wall of his
bedroom which emits mind rays
to soften his brain, 80 The
Divided Self or to send electric
shocks through him while he is
asleep. The person I am
describing feels at this phase
persecuted by reality itself. The
world as it is, and other people as
they are, are the dangers. The
self then seeks by being
unembodied to transcend the
world and hence to be safe. But a
self is liable to develop which
feels it is outside all experience
and activity. It becomes a
vacuum. Everything is there,
outside; nothing is here, inside.
Moreover, the constant dread of
all that is there, of being
overwhelmed, is potentiated
rather than mitigated by the need
to keep the world at bay. Yet the
self may at the same time long
more than anything for
participation in the world. Thus,
its greatest longing is felt as its
greatest weakness and giving in
to this weakness is its greatest
dread, since in participation the
individual fears that his vacuum
will be obliterated, that he will be
engulfed or otherwise lose his
identity, which has come to be
equated with the maintenance of
the transcendence of the self
even though this is a
transcendence in avoid. This
detachment of the self means
that the self is never revealed
directly in the individual's
expressions and actions, nor does
it experience anything
spontaneously or immediately.
The self's relationship to the
other is always at one remove.
The direct and immediate
transactions between the
individual, the other, and the
world, even in such basic
respects as perceiving and
acting, all come to be
meaningless, futile, and false.
One can represent the alternative
state of affairs schematically as
shown opposite. Objects
perceived by the self are
experienced as real. Thoughts
and feelings of which the self is
the agent are alive and are felt to
have point. Actions to which the
self is committed are felt as
genuine. If the individual
delegates all transactions
between himself and the other to
a system within his being which
is not 'him', then the world is
experienced as unreal, and all
that belongs to this system is felt
to be false, futile, and
meaningless. Everyone is subject
to a certain extent at one time or
another to such moods of futility,
meaninglessness, and
purposelessness, but in schizoid
individuals these moods are
particularly insistent. These
moods arise from the fact that the
doors of perception and/or the 82
The Divided Self gates of action
are not in the command of the
self but are being lived and
operated by a false self. The
unrealness of perceptions and the
falsity and meaninglessness of all
activity are the necessary
consequences of perception and
activity being in the command of
a false self- a system partially
dissociated from the 'true' self,
which is, therefore, excluded from
direct participation in the
individual's relatedness with
other persons and the world. A
pseudo-duality is thus
experienced in the individual's
own being. Instead of the
individual meeting the world with
an integral selfhood, he disavows
part of his own being along' with
his disavowal of immediate
attachment to things and people
in the world. This can be
represented schematically as
follows: Instead of (self/body)
other the situation is self
(body-other) The self, therefore, is
precluded from having a direct
relationship with real things and
real people. When this has
happened in patients, one is
witness to the struggle which
ensues to preserve the self's own
sense of its own realness,
aliveness, and identity. In the
first scheme, one has a benign
circle. The reality of the world and
of the self are mutually
potentiated by the direct
relationship between self and
other. In Figure 2, there is a
vicious circle. Every element in
this diagram comes to be
experienced as more and more
unreal and dead. Love is
precluded and dread takes its
place. The final effect is an
overall experience of everything
having come to a stop. Nothing
moves; nothing is alive;
everything is dead, including the
self. The self by its detachment is
precluded from a full experience
of realness and aliveness. What
one might call a creative
relationship with the other, in
which there is mutual enrichment
of the self and the other (benign
circle), is impossible, and an
interaction is substituted which
may seem to operate efficiently
and smoothly for a while but
which has no 'life' in it (sterile
relationship). There is a quasi-it-it
interaction instead of an I-thou
relationship. This interaction is a
dead process. The inner self
seeks to live by certain
(apparently) compensating
advantages. Such a self cherishes
certain ideals. One, which wasThe
Divided Self condition called by
Kierkegaard 'shutupness'. The
individual's actions are not felt as
expressions of his self. His
actions, all that David called his
'personality' and which I have
proposed to call his false-self
system, become dissociated and
partly autonomous. The self is
not felt to participate in the
doings of the false self or selves,
and all its or their actions are felt
to be increasingly false and futile.
The self, on the other hand, shut
up with itself, regards itself as the
'true' self and the persona as
false. The individual complains of
futility, of lack of spontaneity, but
he may be cultivating his lack of
spontaneity and thus aggravating
his sense of futility. He says he is
not real and is outside reality and
not properly alive. Existentially,
he is quite right. The self is
extremely aware of itself, and
observes the false self, usually
highly critically. It is characteristic
of the organization of a false self
or persona, on the other hand,
that one way in which it is usually
incomplete is in its very imperfect
reflective awareness. But the self
may feel itself in danger from the
overall spread of the false-self
system or from one particular
part of it (cf. David's dread of
female impersonation). The
individual in this position is
invariably terrifyingly
'selfconscious ' (see Chapter 7) in
the sense in which this word is
used to mean the exact opposite,
namely, the feeling of being
under observation by the other.
These changes in the relationship
between the different aspects of
the person's relation to himself
are constantly associated with his
inter-personal relationships.
These are complex and never
quite the same from person to
person. The individual's
self-relationship becomes a
pseudo-interpersonal one, and
the self treats the false selves as
though they were other people
whom it depersonalizes. David,
for instance, referring to a part he
played which he found was
disliked, said: 'It had a nasty
tongue.' From within, the self now
looks out at the false things being
said and done and detests the
speaker and doer as though he
were someone else. In all this
there is an attempt to create
relationships to persons and
things within the individual
without recourse to the outer
world of persons and things at
all. The individual is developing a
microcosmos within himself; but,
of course, this autistic, private,
intra-individual 'world' is not a
feasible substitute for the only
world there really is, the shared
The embodied and unembodied
self 75 world. If this were a
feasible project then there would
be no need for psychosis. Such a
schizoid individual in one sense is
trying to be omnipotent by
enclosing within his own being,
without recourse to a creative
relationship with others, modes
of relationship that require the
effective presence to him of other
people and of the outer world. He
would appear to be, in an unreal,
impossible way, all persons and
things to himself. The imagined
advantages are safety for the true
self, isolation and hence freedom
from others, self-sufficiency, and
control. The actual disadvantages
that can be mentioned at this
point are that this project is
impossible and, being a false
hope, leads on to persistent
despair; secondly, a persistent,
haunting sense of futility is the
equally inevitable outcome, since
the hidden shut-up self, in
disowning participation (except,
as David's case, by appearing as
another persona) in the
quasi-autonomous activities of
the falseself systems, is living
only 'mentally'. Moreover, this
shut-up self, being isolated, is
unable to be enriched by outer
experience, and so the whole
inner world comes to be more and
more impoverished, until the
individual may come to feel he is
merely a vacuum. The sense of
being able to do anything and the
feeling of possessing everything
then exist side by side with a
feeling of impotence and
emptiness. The individual who
may at one time have felt
predominantly 'outside' the life
going on there, which he affects
to despise as petty and
commonplace compared to the
richness he has here, inside
himself, now longs to get inside
life again, and get life inside
himself, so dreadful is his inner
deadness. The crucial feature of
the schizoid individual of this type
that we have to understand is the
nature of the anxieties to which
he is subject. We have already
outlined some of the forms these
anxieties take under the terms
engulfment, implosion, and the
dread of losing inner autonomy,
freedom; in short, being turned
from a man with subjectivity to a
thing, a mechanism, a stone, an
it, being petrified. We have yet to
study how these anxieties are
potentiated by the development
of the schizoid organization.
When the self partially abandons
the body and its acts, and
withdraws into mental activity, it
experiences itself as an entity
perhaps localized somewhere in
the body. We have suggested
that 76 The Divided Self this
withdrawal is in part an effort to
preserve its being, since
relationship of any kind with
others is experienced as a threat
to the self's identity. The self feels
safe only in hiding, and isolated.
Such a self can, of course, be
isolated at any time whether
other people are present or not.
But this does not work. No one
feels more 'vulnerable', more
liable to be exposed by the look
of another person than the
schizoid individual. If he is not
acutely aware of being seen by
others ('self-conscious'), he has
temporarily avoided his anxiety
becoming manifest by one or
other of two methods. Either he
turns the other person into a
thing, and depersonalizes or
objectifies his own feelings
towards this thing, or he affects
indifference. The
depersonalization of the person
and/or the attitude of indifference
are closely related but not quite
identical. The depersonalized
person can be used,
manipulated, acted upon. As we
stated above (Chapter 1), the
essential feature of a thing as
opposed to a person is that a
thing has no subjectivity of its
own, and hence can have no
reciprocal intentions. In the
attitude of indifference the person
or thing is treated with
casualness, or callousness, as
though he or it did not matter,
ultimately as though he or it did
not exist. A person minus
subjectivity can still be
important. A thing can still
matter a great deal. Indifference
denies to persons and to things
their significance. Petrification, we
remember, was one of Perseus's
methods of killing his enemies. By
means of the eyes in Medusa's
head, he turned them into
stones. Petrification is one way of
killing. Of course, to feel that
another person is treating or
regarding one not as a person
but as a thing need not itself be
frightening if one is sufficiently
sure of one's own existence.
Thus, being a thing in someone
else's eyes does not represent to
the 'normal' person a catastrophic
threat, but to the schizoid
individual every pair of eyes is in
a Medusa's head which he feels
has power actually to kill or
deaden something precariously
vital in him. He tries therefore to
forestall his own petrification by
turning others into stones. By
doing this he feels he can achieve
some measure of safety.
Generally speaking, the schizoid
individual is not erecting
defences against the loss of a
part of his body. His whole effort
is rather to preserve his self.
This, as we have pointed out, is
pre- The embodied and
unembodied self 77 cariously
established; he is subject to the
dread of his own dissolution into
non-being, into what William
Blake described in the last resort
as 'chaotic non-entity'. His
autonomy is threatened with
engulfment. He has to guard
himself against losing his
subjectivity and sense of being
alive. In so far as he feels empty,
the full, substantial, living reality
of others is an impingement
which is always liable to get out
of hand and become implosive,
threatening to overwhelm and
obliterate his self completely as a
gas will obliterate a vacuum, or as
water will gush in and entirely fill
an empty dam. The schizoid
individual fears a real live
dialectical relationship with real
live people. He can relate himself
only to depersonalized persons,
to phantoms of his own
phantasies (imagos), perhaps to
things, perhaps to animals. We
suggest, therefore, that the
schizoid state we are describing
can be understood as an attempt
to preserve a being that is
precariously structured. We shall
suggest later that the initial
structuralization of being into its
basic elements occurs in early
infancy. In normal circumstances,
this occurs in such a way as to be
so conclusively stable in its basic
elements (for instance, the
continuity of time, the distinction
between the self and not-self,
phantasy and reality), that it can
henceforth be taken for granted:
on this stable base, a
considerable amount of plasticity
can exist in what we call a
person's 'character'. In the
schizoid character structure, on
the other hand, there is an
insecurity in the laying down of
the foundations and a
compensatory rigidity in the
superstructure. If the whole of the
individual's being cannot be
defended, the individual retracts
his lines of defence until he
withdraws within a central
citadel. He is prepared to write off
everything he is, except his 'self'.
But the tragic paradox is that the
more the self is defended in this
way, the more it is destroyed. The
apparent eventual destruction
and dissolution of the self in
schizophrenic conditions is
accomplished not by external
attacks from the enemy (actual
or supposed), from without, but
by the devastation caused by the
inner defensive manoeuvres
themselves. 5 The inner self in
the schizoid condition You can
hold yourself back from the
sufferings of the world, this is
something you are free to do and
is in accord with your nature, but
perhaps precisely this holding
back is the only suffering that you
might be able to avoid. FRANZ
KAFKA In the schizoid condition
here described there is a
persistent scission between the
self and the body. What the
individual regards as his true self
is experienced as more or less
disembodied, and bodily
experience and actions are in turn
felt to be part of the false-self
system. It is now necessary to
consider the two elements in this
split in more detail, and also the
relationship of the one to the
other. First, we consider the
mental or unembodied self. It is
well known that temporary states
of dissociation of the self from the
body occur in normal people. In
general, one can say that it is a
response that appears to be
available to most people who find
themselves enclosed within a
threatening experience from
which there is no physical
escape. Prisoners in concentration
camps tried to feel that way, for
the camp offered no possible way
out either spatially or at the end
of a period of time. The only way
out was by a psychical
withdrawal 'into' one's self and
'out of the body. This dissociation
is characteristically associated
with such thoughts as 'This is like
a dream', 'This seems unreal', 'I
can't believe this is true', 'Nothing
seemed to be touching me', 'I
cannot take it in', 'This is not
happening to me', i.e. with
feelings of estrangement and
derealization. The body may go
on acting in an outwardly normal
way, but inwardly it is felt to be
acting on its own, automatically.
However, despite the
dream-nature or unreality of
experience, and the automatic
nature of action, the self is at the
same time far from 'sleepy';
indeed, it is excessively alert, and
may be thinking and observing
with exceptional lucidity. The
inner self in the schizoid condition
79 The temporary estrangement
of the self from the body may be
represented in dreams. A girl of
nineteen, the date of whose
marriage was fast approaching, a
marriage she had come to dread
for various reasons, dreamed that
she was in the back seat of a car,
which was driving itself. This girl
was not a basically schizoid
person but was reacting by a
schizoid defence to a particular
situation. R. had a dream shortly
before starting treatment. He was
on the footplate of a bus. The bus
had no driver. He jumped off and
the bus went on to crash. One is
tempted to regard a dream he
had after four months of
psychotherapy as a measure of
some change in a desirable
direction. 'I am running after a
bus. Suddenly I'm on the
footplate of the bus, and at the
same time, I'm running after it. I'm
trying to join up with myself on
the bus but I can't entirely catch
up on the bus. I felt frightened at
this.' One could multiply
instances of this common
experience of temporary
dissociation. Sometimes it is
intentionally induced; more
often, it occurs without the
individual's control. But in the
patients here considered, the
splitting is not simply a
temporary reaction to a specific
situation of great danger, which is
reversible when the danger is
past. It is, on the contrary, a basic
orientation to life, and if it is
followed back through their lives
one usually finds that they seem,
in fact, to have emerged from the
early months of infancy with this
split already under way. The
'normal' individual, in a situation
all can see to be threatening to
his being and to offer no real
sense of escape, develops a
schizoid state in trying to get
outside it, if not physically, at
least mentally: he becomes a
mental observer, who looks on,
detached and impassive, at what
his body is doing or what is being
done to his body. If this is so in
the 'normal', it is at least possible
to suppose that the individual
whose abiding mode of
being-in-the-world is of this split
nature is living in what to him, if
not to us, is a world that
threatens his being from all
sides, and from which there is no
exit. This is indeed the case for
such people. For them the world
is a prison without bars, a
concentration camp without
barbed wire. The paranoic has
specific persecutors. Someone is
against him. There is a plot on
foot to steal his brains. A machine
is concealed in the wall of his
bedroom which emits mind rays
to soften his brain, 80 The
Divided Self or to send electric
shocks through him while he is
asleep. The person I am
describing feels at this phase
persecuted by reality itself. The
world as it is, and other people as
they are, are the dangers. The
self then seeks by being
unembodied to transcend the
world and hence to be safe. But a
self is liable to develop which
feels it is outside all experience
and activity. It becomes a
vacuum. Everything is there,
outside; nothing is here, inside.
Moreover, the constant dread of
all that is there, of being
overwhelmed, is potentiated
rather than mitigated by the need
to keep the world at bay. Yet the
self may at the same time long
more than anything for
participation in the world. Thus,
its greatest longing is felt as its
greatest weakness and giving in
to this weakness is its greatest
dread, since in participation the
individual fears that his vacuum
will be obliterated, that he will be
engulfed or otherwise lose his
identity, which has come to be
equated with the maintenance of
the transcendence of the self
even though this is a
transcendence in avoid. This
detachment of the self means
that the self is never revealed
directly in the individual's
expressions and actions, nor does
it experience anything
spontaneously or immediately.
The self's relationship to the
other is always at one remove.
The direct and immediate
transactions between the
individual, the other, and the
world, even in such basic
respects as perceiving and
acting, all come to be
meaningless, futile, and false.
One can represent the alternative
state of affairs schematically as
shown opposite. Objects
perceived by the self are
experienced as real. Thoughts
and feelings of which the self is
the agent are alive and are felt to
have point. Actions to which the
self is committed are felt as
genuine. If the individual
delegates all transactions
between himself and the other to
a system within his being which
is not 'him', then the world is
experienced as unreal, and all
that belongs to this system is felt
to be false, futile, and
meaningless. Everyone is subject
to a certain extent at one time or
another to such moods of futility,
meaninglessness, and
purposelessness, but in schizoid
individuals these moods are
particularly insistent. These
moods arise from the fact that the
doors of perception and/or the 82
The Divided Self gates of action
are not in the command of the
self but are being lived and
operated by a false self. The
unrealness of perceptions and the
falsity and meaninglessness of all
activity are the necessary
consequences of perception and
activity being in the command of
a false self- a system partially
dissociated from the 'true' self,
which is, therefore, excluded from
direct participation in the
individual's relatedness with
other persons and the world. A
pseudo-duality is thus
experienced in the individual's
own being. Instead of the
individual meeting the world with
an integral selfhood, he disavows
part of his own being along' with
his disavowal of immediate
attachment to things and people
in the world. This can be
represented schematically as
follows: Instead of (self/body)
other the situation is self
(body-other) The self, therefore, is
precluded from having a direct
relationship with real things and
real people. When this has
happened in patients, one is
witness to the struggle which
ensues to preserve the self's own
sense of its own realness,
aliveness, and identity. In the
first scheme, one has a benign
circle. The reality of the world and
of the self are mutually
potentiated by the direct
relationship between self and
other. In Figure 2, there is a
vicious circle. Every element in
this diagram comes to be
experienced as more and more
unreal and dead. Love is
precluded and dread takes its
place. The final effect is an
overall experience of everything
having come to a stop. Nothing
moves; nothing is alive;
everything is dead, including the
self. The self by its detachment is
precluded from a full experience
of realness and aliveness. What
one might call a creative
relationship with the other, in
which there is mutual enrichment
of the self and the other (benign
circle), is impossible, and an
interaction is substituted which
may seem to operate efficiently
and smoothly for a while but
which has no 'life' in it (sterile
relationship). There is a quasi-it-it
interaction instead of an I-thou
relationship. This interaction is a
dead process. The inner self
seeks to live by certain
(apparently) compensating
advantages. Such a self cherishes
certain ideals. One, which wasThe
Divided Self condition called by
Kierkegaard 'shutupness'. The
individual's actions are not felt as
expressions of his self. His
actions, all that David called his
'personality' and which I have
proposed to call his false-self
system, become dissociated and
partly autonomous. The self is
not felt to participate in the
doings of the false self or selves,
and all its or their actions are felt
to be increasingly false and futile.
The self, on the other hand, shut
up with itself, regards itself as the
'true' self and the persona as
false. The individual complains of
futility, of lack of spontaneity, but
he may be cultivating his lack of
spontaneity and thus aggravating
his sense of futility. He says he is
not real and is outside reality and
not properly alive. Existentially,
he is quite right. The self is
extremely aware of itself, and
observes the false self, usually
highly critically. It is characteristic
of the organization of a false self
or persona, on the other hand,
that one way in which it is usually
incomplete is in its very imperfect
reflective awareness. But the self
may feel itself in danger from the
overall spread of the false-self
system or from one particular
part of it (cf. David's dread of
female impersonation). The
individual in this position is
invariably terrifyingly
'selfconscious ' (see Chapter 7) in
the sense in which this word is
used to mean the exact opposite,
namely, the feeling of being
under observation by the other.
These changes in the relationship
between the different aspects of
the person's relation to himself
are constantly associated with his
inter-personal relationships.
These are complex and never
quite the same from person to
person. The individual's
self-relationship becomes a
pseudo-interpersonal one, and
the self treats the false selves as
though they were other people
whom it depersonalizes. David,
for instance, referring to a part he
played which he found was
disliked, said: 'It had a nasty
tongue.' From within, the self now
looks out at the false things being
said and done and detests the
speaker and doer as though he
were someone else. In all this
there is an attempt to create
relationships to persons and
things within the individual
without recourse to the outer
world of persons and things at
all. The individual is developing a
microcosmos within himself; but,
of course, this autistic, private,
intra-individual 'world' is not a
feasible substitute for the only
world there really is, the shared
The embodied and unembodied
self 75 world. If this were a
feasible project then there would
be no need for psychosis. Such a
schizoid individual in one sense is
trying to be omnipotent by
enclosing within his own being,
without recourse to a creative
relationship with others, modes
of relationship that require the
effective presence to him of other
people and of the outer world. He
would appear to be, in an unreal,
impossible way, all persons and
things to himself. The imagined
advantages are safety for the true
self, isolation and hence freedom
from others, self-sufficiency, and
control. The actual disadvantages
that can be mentioned at this
point are that this project is
impossible and, being a false
hope, leads on to persistent
despair; secondly, a persistent,
haunting sense of futility is the
equally inevitable outcome, since
the hidden shut-up self, in
disowning participation (except,
as David's case, by appearing as
another persona) in the
quasi-autonomous activities of
the falseself systems, is living
only 'mentally'. Moreover, this
shut-up self, being isolated, is
unable to be enriched by outer
experience, and so the whole
inner world comes to be more and
more impoverished, until the
individual may come to feel he is
merely a vacuum. The sense of
being able to do anything and the
feeling of possessing everything
then exist side by side with a
feeling of impotence and
emptiness. The individual who
may at one time have felt
predominantly 'outside' the life
going on there, which he affects
to despise as petty and
commonplace compared to the
richness he has here, inside
himself, now longs to get inside
life again, and get life inside
himself, so dreadful is his inner
deadness. The crucial feature of
the schizoid individual of this type
that we have to understand is the
nature of the anxieties to which
he is subject. We have already
outlined some of the forms these
anxieties take under the terms
engulfment, implosion, and the
dread of losing inner autonomy,
freedom; in short, being turned
from a man with subjectivity to a
thing, a mechanism, a stone, an
it, being petrified. We have yet to
study how these anxieties are
potentiated by the development
of the schizoid organization.
When the self partially abandons
the body and its acts, and
withdraws into mental activity, it
experiences itself as an entity
perhaps localized somewhere in
the body. We have suggested
that 76 The Divided Self this
withdrawal is in part an effort to
preserve its being, since
relationship of any kind with
others is experienced as a threat
to the self's identity. The self feels
safe only in hiding, and isolated.
Such a self can, of course, be
isolated at any time whether
other people are present or not.
But this does not work. No one
feels more 'vulnerable', more
liable to be exposed by the look
of another person than the
schizoid individual. If he is not
acutely aware of being seen by
others ('self-conscious'), he has
temporarily avoided his anxiety
becoming manifest by one or
other of two methods. Either he
turns the other person into a
thing, and depersonalizes or
objectifies his own feelings
towards this thing, or he affects
indifference. The
depersonalization of the person
and/or the attitude of indifference
are closely related but not quite
identical. The depersonalized
person can be used,
manipulated, acted upon. As we
stated above (Chapter 1), the
essential feature of a thing as
opposed to a person is that a
thing has no subjectivity of its
own, and hence can have no
reciprocal intentions. In the
attitude of indifference the person
or thing is treated with
casualness, or callousness, as
though he or it did not matter,
ultimately as though he or it did
not exist. A person minus
subjectivity can still be
important. A thing can still
matter a great deal. Indifference
denies to persons and to things
their significance. Petrification, we
remember, was one of Perseus's
methods of killing his enemies. By
means of the eyes in Medusa's
head, he turned them into
stones. Petrification is one way of
killing. Of course, to feel that
another person is treating or
regarding one not as a person
but as a thing need not itself be
frightening if one is sufficiently
sure of one's own existence.
Thus, being a thing in someone
else's eyes does not represent to
the 'normal' person a catastrophic
threat, but to the schizoid
individual every pair of eyes is in
a Medusa's head which he feels
has power actually to kill or
deaden something precariously
vital in him. He tries therefore to
forestall his own petrification by
turning others into stones. By
doing this he feels he can achieve
some measure of safety.
Generally speaking, the schizoid
individual is not erecting
defences against the loss of a
part of his body. His whole effort
is rather to preserve his self.
This, as we have pointed out, is
pre- The embodied and
unembodied self 77 cariously
established; he is subject to the
dread of his own dissolution into
non-being, into what William
Blake described in the last resort
as 'chaotic non-entity'. His
autonomy is threatened with
engulfment. He has to guard
himself against losing his
subjectivity and sense of being
alive. In so far as he feels empty,
the full, substantial, living reality
of others is an impingement
which is always liable to get out
of hand and become implosive,
threatening to overwhelm and
obliterate his self completely as a
gas will obliterate a vacuum, or as
water will gush in and entirely fill
an empty dam. The schizoid
individual fears a real live
dialectical relationship with real
live people. He can relate himself
only to depersonalized persons,
to phantoms of his own
phantasies (imagos), perhaps to
things, perhaps to animals. We
suggest, therefore, that the
schizoid state we are describing
can be understood as an attempt
to preserve a being that is
precariously structured. We shall
suggest later that the initial
structuralization of being into its
basic elements occurs in early
infancy. In normal circumstances,
this occurs in such a way as to be
so conclusively stable in its basic
elements (for instance, the
continuity of time, the distinction
between the self and not-self,
phantasy and reality), that it can
henceforth be taken for granted:
on this stable base, a
considerable amount of plasticity
can exist in what we call a
person's 'character'. In the
schizoid character structure, on
the other hand, there is an
insecurity in the laying down of
the foundations and a
compensatory rigidity in the
superstructure. If the whole of the
individual's being cannot be
defended, the individual retracts
his lines of defence until he
withdraws within a central
citadel. He is prepared to write off
everything he is, except his 'self'.
But the tragic paradox is that the
more the self is defended in this
way, the more it is destroyed. The
apparent eventual destruction
and dissolution of the self in
schizophrenic conditions is
accomplished not by external
attacks from the enemy (actual
or supposed), from without, but
by the devastation caused by the
inner defensive manoeuvres
themselves. 5 The inner self in
the schizoid condition You can
hold yourself back from the
sufferings of the world, this is
something you are free to do and
is in accord with your nature, but
perhaps precisely this holding
back is the only suffering that you
might be able to avoid. FRANZ
KAFKA In the schizoid condition
here described there is a
persistent scission between the
self and the body. What the
individual regards as his true self
is experienced as more or less
disembodied, and bodily
experience and actions are in turn
felt to be part of the false-self
system. It is now necessary to
consider the two elements in this
split in more detail, and also the
relationship of the one to the
other. First, we consider the
mental or unembodied self. It is
well known that temporary states
of dissociation of the self from the
body occur in normal people. In
general, one can say that it is a
response that appears to be
available to most people who find
themselves enclosed within a
threatening experience from
which there is no physical
escape. Prisoners in concentration
camps tried to feel that way, for
the camp offered no possible way
out either spatially or at the end
of a period of time. The only way
out was by a psychical
withdrawal 'into' one's self and
'out of the body. This dissociation
is characteristically associated
with such thoughts as 'This is like
a dream', 'This seems unreal', 'I
can't believe this is true', 'Nothing
seemed to be touching me', 'I
cannot take it in', 'This is not
happening to me', i.e. with
feelings of estrangement and
derealization. The body may go
on acting in an outwardly normal
way, but inwardly it is felt to be
acting on its own, automatically.
However, despite the
dream-nature or unreality of
experience, and the automatic
nature of action, the self is at the
same time far from 'sleepy';
indeed, it is excessively alert, and
may be thinking and observing
with exceptional lucidity. The
inner self in the schizoid condition
79 The temporary estrangement
of the self from the body may be
represented in dreams. A girl of
nineteen, the date of whose
marriage was fast approaching, a
marriage she had come to dread
for various reasons, dreamed that
she was in the back seat of a car,
which was driving itself. This girl
was not a basically schizoid
person but was reacting by a
schizoid defence to a particular
situation. R. had a dream shortly
before starting treatment. He was
on the footplate of a bus. The bus
had no driver. He jumped off and
the bus went on to crash. One is
tempted to regard a dream he
had after four months of
psychotherapy as a measure of
some change in a desirable
direction. 'I am running after a
bus. Suddenly I'm on the
footplate of the bus, and at the
same time, I'm running after it. I'm
trying to join up with myself on
the bus but I can't entirely catch
up on the bus. I felt frightened at
this.' One could multiply
instances of this common
experience of temporary
dissociation. Sometimes it is
intentionally induced; more
often, it occurs without the
individual's control. But in the
patients here considered, the
splitting is not simply a
temporary reaction to a specific
situation of great danger, which is
reversible when the danger is
past. It is, on the contrary, a basic
orientation to life, and if it is
followed back through their lives
one usually finds that they seem,
in fact, to have emerged from the
early months of infancy with this
split already under way. The
'normal' individual, in a situation
all can see to be threatening to
his being and to offer no real
sense of escape, develops a
schizoid state in trying to get
outside it, if not physically, at
least mentally: he becomes a
mental observer, who looks on,
detached and impassive, at what
his body is doing or what is being
done to his body. If this is so in
the 'normal', it is at least possible
to suppose that the individual
whose abiding mode of
being-in-the-world is of this split
nature is living in what to him, if
not to us, is a world that
threatens his being from all
sides, and from which there is no
exit. This is indeed the case for
such people. For them the world
is a prison without bars, a
concentration camp without
barbed wire. The paranoic has
specific persecutors. Someone is
against him. There is a plot on
foot to steal his brains. A machine
is concealed in the wall of his
bedroom which emits mind rays
to soften his brain, 80 The
Divided Self or to send electric
shocks through him while he is
asleep. The person I am
describing feels at this phase
persecuted by reality itself. The
world as it is, and other people as
they are, are the dangers. The
self then seeks by being
unembodied to transcend the
world and hence to be safe. But a
self is liable to develop which
feels it is outside all experience
and activity. It becomes a
vacuum. Everything is there,
outside; nothing is here, inside.
Moreover, the constant dread of
all that is there, of being
overwhelmed, is potentiated
rather than mitigated by the need
to keep the world at bay. Yet the
self may at the same time long
more than anything for
participation in the world. Thus,
its greatest longing is felt as its
greatest weakness and giving in
to this weakness is its greatest
dread, since in participation the
individual fears that his vacuum
will be obliterated, that he will be
engulfed or otherwise lose his
identity, which has come to be
equated with the maintenance of
the transcendence of the self
even though this is a
transcendence in avoid. This
detachment of the self means
that the self is never revealed
directly in the individual's
expressions and actions, nor does
it experience anything
spontaneously or immediately.
The self's relationship to the
other is always at one remove.
The direct and immediate
transactions between the
individual, the other, and the
world, even in such basic
respects as perceiving and
acting, all come to be
meaningless, futile, and false.
One can represent the alternative
state of affairs schematically as
shown opposite. Objects
perceived by the self are
experienced as real. Thoughts
and feelings of which the self is
the agent are alive and are felt to
have point. Actions to which the
self is committed are felt as
genuine. If the individual
delegates all transactions
between himself and the other to
a system within his being which
is not 'him', then the world is
experienced as unreal, and all
that belongs to this system is felt
to be false, futile, and
meaningless. Everyone is subject
to a certain extent at one time or
another to such moods of futility,
meaninglessness, and
purposelessness, but in schizoid
individuals these moods are
particularly insistent. These
moods arise from the fact that the
doors of perception and/or the 82
The Divided Self gates of action
are not in the command of the
self but are being lived and
operated by a false self. The
unrealness of perceptions and the
falsity and meaninglessness of all
activity are the necessary
consequences of perception and
activity being in the command of
a false self- a system partially
dissociated from the 'true' self,
which is, therefore, excluded from
direct participation in the
individual's relatedness with
other persons and the world. A
pseudo-duality is thus
experienced in the individual's
own being. Instead of the
individual meeting the world with
an integral selfhood, he disavows
part of his own being along' with
his disavowal of immediate
attachment to things and people
in the world. This can be
represented schematically as
follows: Instead of (self/body)
other the situation is self
(body-other) The self, therefore, is
precluded from having a direct
relationship with real things and
real people. When this has
happened in patients, one is
witness to the struggle which
ensues to preserve the self's own
sense of its own realness,
aliveness, and identity. In the
first scheme, one has a benign
circle. The reality of the world and
of the self are mutually
potentiated by the direct
relationship between self and
other. In Figure 2, there is a
vicious circle. Every element in
this diagram comes to be
experienced as more and more
unreal and dead. Love is
precluded and dread takes its
place. The final effect is an
overall experience of everything
having come to a stop. Nothing
moves; nothing is alive;
everything is dead, including the
self. The self by its detachment is
precluded from a full experience
of realness and aliveness. What
one might call a creative
relationship with the other, in
which there is mutual enrichment
of the self and the other (benign
circle), is impossible, and an
interaction is substituted which
may seem to operate efficiently
and smoothly for a while but
which has no 'life' in it (sterile
relationship). There is a quasi-it-it
interaction instead of an I-thou
relationship. This interaction is a
dead process. The inner self
seeks to live by certain
(apparently) compensating
advantages. Such a self cherishes
certain ideals. One, which wasThe
Divided Self condition called by
Kierkegaard 'shutupness'. The
individual's actions are not felt as
expressions of his self. His
actions, all that David called his
'personality' and which I have
proposed to call his false-self
system, become dissociated and
partly autonomous. The self is
not felt to participate in the
doings of the false self or selves,
and all its or their actions are felt
to be increasingly false and futile.
The self, on the other hand, shut
up with itself, regards itself as the
'true' self and the persona as
false. The individual complains of
futility, of lack of spontaneity, but
he may be cultivating his lack of
spontaneity and thus aggravating
his sense of futility. He says he is
not real and is outside reality and
not properly alive. Existentially,
he is quite right. The self is
extremely aware of itself, and
observes the false self, usually
highly critically. It is characteristic
of the organization of a false self
or persona, on the other hand,
that one way in which it is usually
incomplete is in its very imperfect
reflective awareness. But the self
may feel itself in danger from the
overall spread of the false-self
system or from one particular
part of it (cf. David's dread of
female impersonation). The
individual in this position is
invariably terrifyingly
'selfconscious ' (see Chapter 7) in
the sense in which this word is
used to mean the exact opposite,
namely, the feeling of being
under observation by the other.
These changes in the relationship
between the different aspects of
the person's relation to himself
are constantly associated with his
inter-personal relationships.
These are complex and never
quite the same from person to
person. The individual's
self-relationship becomes a
pseudo-interpersonal one, and
the self treats the false selves as
though they were other people
whom it depersonalizes. David,
for instance, referring to a part he
played which he found was
disliked, said: 'It had a nasty
tongue.' From within, the self now
looks out at the false things being
said and done and detests the
speaker and doer as though he
were someone else. In all this
there is an attempt to create
relationships to persons and
things within the individual
without recourse to the outer
world of persons and things at
all. The individual is developing a
microcosmos within himself; but,
of course, this autistic, private,
intra-individual 'world' is not a
feasible substitute for the only
world there really is, the shared
The embodied and unembodied
self 75 world. If this were a
feasible project then there would
be no need for psychosis. Such a
schizoid individual in one sense is
trying to be omnipotent by
enclosing within his own being,
without recourse to a creative
relationship with others, modes
of relationship that require the
effective presence to him of other
people and of the outer world. He
would appear to be, in an unreal,
impossible way, all persons and
things to himself. The imagined
advantages are safety for the true
self, isolation and hence freedom
from others, self-sufficiency, and
control. The actual disadvantages
that can be mentioned at this
point are that this project is
impossible and, being a false
hope, leads on to persistent
despair; secondly, a persistent,
haunting sense of futility is the
equally inevitable outcome, since
the hidden shut-up self, in
disowning participation (except,
as David's case, by appearing as
another persona) in the
quasi-autonomous activities of
the falseself systems, is living
only 'mentally'. Moreover, this
shut-up self, being isolated, is
unable to be enriched by outer
experience, and so the whole
inner world comes to be more and
more impoverished, until the
individual may come to feel he is
merely a vacuum. The sense of
being able to do anything and the
feeling of possessing everything
then exist side by side with a
feeling of impotence and
emptiness. The individual who
may at one time have felt
predominantly 'outside' the life
going on there, which he affects
to despise as petty and
commonplace compared to the
richness he has here, inside
himself, now longs to get inside
life again, and get life inside
himself, so dreadful is his inner
deadness. The crucial feature of
the schizoid individual of this type
that we have to understand is the
nature of the anxieties to which
he is subject. We have already
outlined some of the forms these
anxieties take under the terms
engulfment, implosion, and the
dread of losing inner autonomy,
freedom; in short, being turned
from a man with subjectivity to a
thing, a mechanism, a stone, an
it, being petrified. We have yet to
study how these anxieties are
potentiated by the development
of the schizoid organization.
When the self partially abandons
the body and its acts, and
withdraws into mental activity, it
experiences itself as an entity
perhaps localized somewhere in
the body. We have suggested
that 76 The Divided Self this
withdrawal is in part an effort to
preserve its being, since
relationship of any kind with
others is experienced as a threat
to the self's identity. The self feels
safe only in hiding, and isolated.
Such a self can, of course, be
isolated at any time whether
other people are present or not.
But this does not work. No one
feels more 'vulnerable', more
liable to be exposed by the look
of another person than the
schizoid individual. If he is not
acutely aware of being seen by
others ('self-conscious'), he has
temporarily avoided his anxiety
becoming manifest by one or
other of two methods. Either he
turns the other person into a
thing, and depersonalizes or
objectifies his own feelings
towards this thing, or he affects
indifference. The
depersonalization of the person
and/or the attitude of indifference
are closely related but not quite
identical. The depersonalized
person can be used,
manipulated, acted upon. As we
stated above (Chapter 1), the
essential feature of a thing as
opposed to a person is that a
thing has no subjectivity of its
own, and hence can have no
reciprocal intentions. In the
attitude of indifference the person
or thing is treated with
casualness, or callousness, as
though he or it did not matter,
ultimately as though he or it did
not exist. A person minus
subjectivity can still be
important. A thing can still
matter a great deal. Indifference
denies to persons and to things
their significance. Petrification, we
remember, was one of Perseus's
methods of killing his enemies. By
means of the eyes in Medusa's
head, he turned them into
stones. Petrification is one way of
killing. Of course, to feel that
another person is treating or
regarding one not as a person
but as a thing need not itself be
frightening if one is sufficiently
sure of one's own existence.
Thus, being a thing in someone
else's eyes does not represent to
the 'normal' person a catastrophic
threat, but to the schizoid
individual every pair of eyes is in
a Medusa's head which he feels
has power actually to kill or
deaden something precariously
vital in him. He tries therefore to
forestall his own petrification by
turning others into stones. By
doing this he feels he can achieve
some measure of safety.
Generally speaking, the schizoid
individual is not erecting
defences against the loss of a
part of his body. His whole effort
is rather to preserve his self.
This, as we have pointed out, is
pre- The embodied and
unembodied self 77 cariously
established; he is subject to the
dread of his own dissolution into
non-being, into what William
Blake described in the last resort
as 'chaotic non-entity'. His
autonomy is threatened with
engulfment. He has to guard
himself against losing his
subjectivity and sense of being
alive. In so far as he feels empty,
the full, substantial, living reality
of others is an impingement
which is always liable to get out
of hand and become implosive,
threatening to overwhelm and
obliterate his self completely as a
gas will obliterate a vacuum, or as
water will gush in and entirely fill
an empty dam. The schizoid
individual fears a real live
dialectical relationship with real
live people. He can relate himself
only to depersonalized persons,
to phantoms of his own
phantasies (imagos), perhaps to
things, perhaps to animals. We
suggest, therefore, that the
schizoid state we are describing
can be understood as an attempt
to preserve a being that is
precariously structured. We shall
suggest later that the initial
structuralization of being into its
basic elements occurs in early
infancy. In normal circumstances,
this occurs in such a way as to be
so conclusively stable in its basic
elements (for instance, the
continuity of time, the distinction
between the self and not-self,
phantasy and reality), that it can
henceforth be taken for granted:
on this stable base, a
considerable amount of plasticity
can exist in what we call a
person's 'character'. In the
schizoid character structure, on
the other hand, there is an
insecurity in the laying down of
the foundations and a
compensatory rigidity in the
superstructure. If the whole of the
individual's being cannot be
defended, the individual retracts
his lines of defence until he
withdraws within a central
citadel. He is prepared to write off
everything he is, except his 'self'.
But the tragic paradox is that the
more the self is defended in this
way, the more it is destroyed. The
apparent eventual destruction
and dissolution of the self in
schizophrenic conditions is
accomplished not by external
attacks from the enemy (actual
or supposed), from without, but
by the devastation caused by the
inner defensive manoeuvres
themselves. 5 The inner self in
the schizoid condition You can
hold yourself back from the
sufferings of the world, this is
something you are free to do and
is in accord with your nature, but
perhaps precisely this holding
back is the only suffering that you
might be able to avoid. FRANZ
KAFKA In the schizoid condition
here described there is a
persistent scission between the
self and the body. What the
individual regards as his true self
is experienced as more or less
disembodied, and bodily
experience and actions are in turn
felt to be part of the false-self
system. It is now necessary to
consider the two elements in this
split in more detail, and also the
relationship of the one to the
other. First, we consider the
mental or unembodied self. It is
well known that temporary states
of dissociation of the self from the
body occur in normal people. In
general, one can say that it is a
response that appears to be
available to most people who find
themselves enclosed within a
threatening experience from
which there is no physical
escape. Prisoners in concentration
camps tried to feel that way, for
the camp offered no possible way
out either spatially or at the end
of a period of time. The only way
out was by a psychical
withdrawal 'into' one's self and
'out of the body. This dissociation
is characteristically associated
with such thoughts as 'This is like
a dream', 'This seems unreal', 'I
can't believe this is true', 'Nothing
seemed to be touching me', 'I
cannot take it in', 'This is not
happening to me', i.e. with
feelings of estrangement and
derealization. The body may go
on acting in an outwardly normal
way, but inwardly it is felt to be
acting on its own, automatically.
However, despite the
dream-nature or unreality of
experience, and the automatic
nature of action, the self is at the
same time far from 'sleepy';
indeed, it is excessively alert, and
may be thinking and observing
with exceptional lucidity. The
inner self in the schizoid condition
79 The temporary estrangement
of the self from the body may be
represented in dreams. A girl of
nineteen, the date of whose
marriage was fast approaching, a
marriage she had come to dread
for various reasons, dreamed that
she was in the back seat of a car,
which was driving itself. This girl
was not a basically schizoid
person but was reacting by a
schizoid defence to a particular
situation. R. had a dream shortly
before starting treatment. He was
on the footplate of a bus. The bus
had no driver. He jumped off and
the bus went on to crash. One is
tempted to regard a dream he
had after four months of
psychotherapy as a measure of
some change in a desirable
direction. 'I am running after a
bus. Suddenly I'm on the
footplate of the bus, and at the
same time, I'm running after it. I'm
trying to join up with myself on
the bus but I can't entirely catch
up on the bus. I felt frightened at
this.' One could multiply
instances of this common
experience of temporary
dissociation. Sometimes it is
intentionally induced; more
often, it occurs without the
individual's control. But in the
patients here considered, the
splitting is not simply a
temporary reaction to a specific
situation of great danger, which is
reversible when the danger is
past. It is, on the contrary, a basic
orientation to life, and if it is
followed back through their lives
one usually finds that they seem,
in fact, to have emerged from the
early months of infancy with this
split already under way. The
'normal' individual, in a situation
all can see to be threatening to
his being and to offer no real
sense of escape, develops a
schizoid state in trying to get
outside it, if not physically, at
least mentally: he becomes a
mental observer, who looks on,
detached and impassive, at what
his body is doing or what is being
done to his body. If this is so in
the 'normal', it is at least possible
to suppose that the individual
whose abiding mode of
being-in-the-world is of this split
nature is living in what to him, if
not to us, is a world that
threatens his being from all
sides, and from which there is no
exit. This is indeed the case for
such people. For them the world
is a prison without bars, a
concentration camp without
barbed wire. The paranoic has
specific persecutors. Someone is
against him. There is a plot on
foot to steal his brains. A machine
is concealed in the wall of his
bedroom which emits mind rays
to soften his brain, 80 The
Divided Self or to send electric
shocks through him while he is
asleep. The person I am
describing feels at this phase
persecuted by reality itself. The
world as it is, and other people as
they are, are the dangers. The
self then seeks by being
unembodied to transcend the
world and hence to be safe. But a
self is liable to develop which
feels it is outside all experience
and activity. It becomes a
vacuum. Everything is there,
outside; nothing is here, inside.
Moreover, the constant dread of
all that is there, of being
overwhelmed, is potentiated
rather than mitigated by the need
to keep the world at bay. Yet the
self may at the same time long
more than anything for
participation in the world. Thus,
its greatest longing is felt as its
greatest weakness and giving in
to this weakness is its greatest
dread, since in participation the
individual fears that his vacuum
will be obliterated, that he will be
engulfed or otherwise lose his
identity, which has come to be
equated with the maintenance of
the transcendence of the self
even though this is a
transcendence in avoid. This
detachment of the self means
that the self is never revealed
directly in the individual's
expressions and actions, nor does
it experience anything
spontaneously or immediately.
The self's relationship to the
other is always at one remove.
The direct and immediate
transactions between the
individual, the other, and the
world, even in such basic
respects as perceiving and
acting, all come to be
meaningless, futile, and false.
One can represent the alternative
state of affairs schematically as
shown opposite. Objects
perceived by the self are
experienced as real. Thoughts
and feelings of which the self is
the agent are alive and are felt to
have point. Actions to which the
self is committed are felt as
genuine. If the individual
delegates all transactions
between himself and the other to
a system within his being which
is not 'him', then the world is
experienced as unreal, and all
that belongs to this system is felt
to be false, futile, and
meaningless. Everyone is subject
to a certain extent at one time or
another to such moods of futility,
meaninglessness, and
purposelessness, but in schizoid
individuals these moods are
particularly insistent. These
moods arise from the fact that the
doors of perception and/or the 82
The Divided Self gates of action
are not in the command of the
self but are being lived and
operated by a false self. The
unrealness of perceptions and the
falsity and meaninglessness of all
activity are the necessary
consequences of perception and
activity being in the command of
a false self- a system partially
dissociated from the 'true' self,
which is, therefore, excluded from
direct participation in the
individual's relatedness with
other persons and the world. A
pseudo-duality is thus
experienced in the individual's
own being. Instead of the
individual meeting the world with
an integral selfhood, he disavows
part of his own being along' with
his disavowal of immediate
attachment to things and people
in the world. This can be
represented schematically as
follows: Instead of (self/body)
other the situation is self
(body-other) The self, therefore, is
precluded from having a direct
relationship with real things and
real people. When this has
happened in patients, one is
witness to the struggle which
ensues to preserve the self's own
sense of its own realness,
aliveness, and identity. In the
first scheme, one has a benign
circle. The reality of the world and
of the self are mutually
potentiated by the direct
relationship between self and
other. In Figure 2, there is a
vicious circle. Every element in
this diagram comes to be
experienced as more and more
unreal and dead. Love is
precluded and dread takes its
place. The final effect is an
overall experience of everything
having come to a stop. Nothing
moves; nothing is alive;
everything is dead, including the
self. The self by its detachment is
precluded from a full experience
of realness and aliveness. What
one might call a creative
relationship with the other, in
which there is mutual enrichment
of the self and the other (benign
circle), is impossible, and an
interaction is substituted which
may seem to operate efficiently
and smoothly for a while but
which has no 'life' in it (sterile
relationship). There is a quasi-it-it
interaction instead of an I-thou
relationship. This interaction is a
dead process. The inner self
seeks to live by certain
(apparently) compensating
advantages. Such a self cherishes
certain ideals. One, which wasThe
Divided Self condition called by
Kierkegaard 'shutupness'. The
individual's actions are not felt as
expressions of his self. His
actions, all that David called his
'personality' and which I have
proposed to call his false-self
system, become dissociated and
partly autonomous. The self is
not felt to participate in the
doings of the false self or selves,
and all its or their actions are felt
to be increasingly false and futile.
The self, on the other hand, shut
up with itself, regards itself as the
'true' self and the persona as
false. The individual complains of
futility, of lack of spontaneity, but
he may be cultivating his lack of
spontaneity and thus aggravating
his sense of futility. He says he is
not real and is outside reality and
not properly alive. Existentially,
he is quite right. The self is
extremely aware of itself, and
observes the false self, usually
highly critically. It is characteristic
of the organization of a false self
or persona, on the other hand,
that one way in which it is usually
incomplete is in its very imperfect
reflective awareness. But the self
may feel itself in danger from the
overall spread of the false-self
system or from one particular
part of it (cf. David's dread of
female impersonation). The
individual in this position is
invariably terrifyingly
'selfconscious ' (see Chapter 7) in
the sense in which this word is
used to mean the exact opposite,
namely, the feeling of being
under observation by the other.
These changes in the relationship
between the different aspects of
the person's relation to himself
are constantly associated with his
inter-personal relationships.
These are complex and never
quite the same from person to
person. The individual's
self-relationship becomes a
pseudo-interpersonal one, and
the self treats the false selves as
though they were other people
whom it depersonalizes. David,
for instance, referring to a part he
played which he found was
disliked, said: 'It had a nasty
tongue.' From within, the self now
looks out at the false things being
said and done and detests the
speaker and doer as though he
were someone else. In all this
there is an attempt to create
relationships to persons and
things within the individual
without recourse to the outer
world of persons and things at
all. The individual is developing a
microcosmos within himself; but,
of course, this autistic, private,
intra-individual 'world' is not a
feasible substitute for the only
world there really is, the shared
The embodied and unembodied
self 75 world. If this were a
feasible project then there would
be no need for psychosis. Such a
schizoid individual in one sense is
trying to be omnipotent by
enclosing within his own being,
without recourse to a creative
relationship with others, modes
of relationship that require the
effective presence to him of other
people and of the outer world. He
would appear to be, in an unreal,
impossible way, all persons and
things to himself. The imagined
advantages are safety for the true
self, isolation and hence freedom
from others, self-sufficiency, and
control. The actual disadvantages
that can be mentioned at this
point are that this project is
impossible and, being a false
hope, leads on to persistent
despair; secondly, a persistent,
haunting sense of futility is the
equally inevitable outcome, since
the hidden shut-up self, in
disowning participation (except,
as David's case, by appearing as
another persona) in the
quasi-autonomous activities of
the falseself systems, is living
only 'mentally'. Moreover, this
shut-up self, being isolated, is
unable to be enriched by outer
experience, and so the whole
inner world comes to be more and
more impoverished, until the
individual may come to feel he is
merely a vacuum. The sense of
being able to do anything and the
feeling of possessing everything
then exist side by side with a
feeling of impotence and
emptiness. The individual who
may at one time have felt
predominantly 'outside' the life
going on there, which he affects
to despise as petty and
commonplace compared to the
richness he has here, inside
himself, now longs to get inside
life again, and get life inside
himself, so dreadful is his inner
deadness. The crucial feature of
the schizoid individual of this type
that we have to understand is the
nature of the anxieties to which
he is subject. We have already
outlined some of the forms these
anxieties take under the terms
engulfment, implosion, and the
dread of losing inner autonomy,
freedom; in short, being turned
from a man with subjectivity to a
thing, a mechanism, a stone, an
it, being petrified. We have yet to
study how these anxieties are
potentiated by the development
of the schizoid organization.
When the self partially abandons
the body and its acts, and
withdraws into mental activity, it
experiences itself as an entity
perhaps localized somewhere in
the body. We have suggested
that 76 The Divided Self this
withdrawal is in part an effort to
preserve its being, since
relationship of any kind with
others is experienced as a threat
to the self's identity. The self feels
safe only in hiding, and isolated.
Such a self can, of course, be
isolated at any time whether
other people are present or not.
But this does not work. No one
feels more 'vulnerable', more
liable to be exposed by the look
of another person than the
schizoid individual. If he is not
acutely aware of being seen by
others ('self-conscious'), he has
temporarily avoided his anxiety
becoming manifest by one or
other of two methods. Either he
turns the other person into a
thing, and depersonalizes or
objectifies his own feelings
towards this thing, or he affects
indifference. The
depersonalization of the person
and/or the attitude of indifference
are closely related but not quite
identical. The depersonalized
person can be used,
manipulated, acted upon. As we
stated above (Chapter 1), the
essential feature of a thing as
opposed to a person is that a
thing has no subjectivity of its
own, and hence can have no
reciprocal intentions. In the
attitude of indifference the person
or thing is treated with
casualness, or callousness, as
though he or it did not matter,
ultimately as though he or it did
not exist. A person minus
subjectivity can still be
important. A thing can still
matter a great deal. Indifference
denies to persons and to things
their significance. Petrification, we
remember, was one of Perseus's
methods of killing his enemies. By
means of the eyes in Medusa's
head, he turned them into
stones. Petrification is one way of
killing. Of course, to feel that
another person is treating or
regarding one not as a person
but as a thing need not itself be
frightening if one is sufficiently
sure of one's own existence.
Thus, being a thing in someone
else's eyes does not represent to
the 'normal' person a catastrophic
threat, but to the schizoid
individual every pair of eyes is in
a Medusa's head which he feels
has power actually to kill or
deaden something precariously
vital in him. He tries therefore to
forestall his own petrification by
turning others into stones. By
doing this he feels he can achieve
some measure of safety.
Generally speaking, the schizoid
individual is not erecting
defences against the loss of a
part of his body. His whole effort
is rather to preserve his self.
This, as we have pointed out, is
pre- The embodied and
unembodied self 77 cariously
established; he is subject to the
dread of his own dissolution into
non-being, into what William
Blake described in the last resort
as 'chaotic non-entity'. His
autonomy is threatened with
engulfment. He has to guard
himself against losing his
subjectivity and sense of being
alive. In so far as he feels empty,
the full, substantial, living reality
of others is an impingement
which is always liable to get out
of hand and become implosive,
threatening to overwhelm and
obliterate his self completely as a
gas will obliterate a vacuum, or as
water will gush in and entirely fill
an empty dam. The schizoid
individual fears a real live
dialectical relationship with real
live people. He can relate himself
only to depersonalized persons,
to phantoms of his own
phantasies (imagos), perhaps to
things, perhaps to animals. We
suggest, therefore, that the
schizoid state we are describing
can be understood as an attempt
to preserve a being that is
precariously structured. We shall
suggest later that the initial
structuralization of being into its
basic elements occurs in early
infancy. In normal circumstances,
this occurs in such a way as to be
so conclusively stable in its basic
elements (for instance, the
continuity of time, the distinction
between the self and not-self,
phantasy and reality), that it can
henceforth be taken for granted:
on this stable base, a
considerable amount of plasticity
can exist in what we call a
person's 'character'. In the
schizoid character structure, on
the other hand, there is an
insecurity in the laying down of
the foundations and a
compensatory rigidity in the
superstructure. If the whole of the
individual's being cannot be
defended, the individual retracts
his lines of defence until he
withdraws within a central
citadel. He is prepared to write off
everything he is, except his 'self'.
But the tragic paradox is that the
more the self is defended in this
way, the more it is destroyed. The
apparent eventual destruction
and dissolution of the self in
schizophrenic conditions is
accomplished not by external
attacks from the enemy (actual
or supposed), from without, but
by the devastation caused by the
inner defensive manoeuvres
themselves. 5 The inner self in
the schizoid condition You can
hold yourself back from the
sufferings of the world, this is
something you are free to do and
is in accord with your nature, but
perhaps precisely this holding
back is the only suffering that you
might be able to avoid. FRANZ
KAFKA In the schizoid condition
here described there is a
persistent scission between the
self and the body. What the
individual regards as his true self
is experienced as more or less
disembodied, and bodily
experience and actions are in turn
felt to be part of the false-self
system. It is now necessary to
consider the two elements in this
split in more detail, and also the
relationship of the one to the
other. First, we consider the
mental or unembodied self. It is
well known that temporary states
of dissociation of the self from the
body occur in normal people. In
general, one can say that it is a
response that appears to be
available to most people who find
themselves enclosed within a
threatening experience from
which there is no physical
escape. Prisoners in concentration
camps tried to feel that way, for
the camp offered no possible way
out either spatially or at the end
of a period of time. The only way
out was by a psychical
withdrawal 'into' one's self and
'out of the body. This dissociation
is characteristically associated
with such thoughts as 'This is like
a dream', 'This seems unreal', 'I
can't believe this is true', 'Nothing
seemed to be touching me', 'I
cannot take it in', 'This is not
happening to me', i.e. with
feelings of estrangement and
derealization. The body may go
on acting in an outwardly normal
way, but inwardly it is felt to be
acting on its own, automatically.
However, despite the
dream-nature or unreality of
experience, and the automatic
nature of action, the self is at the
same time far from 'sleepy';
indeed, it is excessively alert, and
may be thinking and observing
with exceptional lucidity. The
inner self in the schizoid condition
79 The temporary estrangement
of the self from the body may be
represented in dreams. A girl of
nineteen, the date of whose
marriage was fast approaching, a
marriage she had come to dread
for various reasons, dreamed that
she was in the back seat of a car,
which was driving itself. This girl
was not a basically schizoid
person but was reacting by a
schizoid defence to a particular
situation. R. had a dream shortly
before starting treatment. He was
on the footplate of a bus. The bus
had no driver. He jumped off and
the bus went on to crash. One is
tempted to regard a dream he
had after four months of
psychotherapy as a measure of
some change in a desirable
direction. 'I am running after a
bus. Suddenly I'm on the
footplate of the bus, and at the
same time, I'm running after it. I'm
trying to join up with myself on
the bus but I can't entirely catch
up on the bus. I felt frightened at
this.' One could multiply
instances of this common
experience of temporary
dissociation. Sometimes it is
intentionally induced; more
often, it occurs without the
individual's control. But in the
patients here considered, the
splitting is not simply a
temporary reaction to a specific
situation of great danger, which is
reversible when the danger is
past. It is, on the contrary, a basic
orientation to life, and if it is
followed back through their lives
one usually finds that they seem,
in fact, to have emerged from the
early months of infancy with this
split already under way. The
'normal' individual, in a situation
all can see to be threatening to
his being and to offer no real
sense of escape, develops a
schizoid state in trying to get
outside it, if not physically, at
least mentally: he becomes a
mental observer, who looks on,
detached and impassive, at what
his body is doing or what is being
done to his body. If this is so in
the 'normal', it is at least possible
to suppose that the individual
whose abiding mode of
being-in-the-world is of this split
nature is living in what to him, if
not to us, is a world that
threatens his being from all
sides, and from which there is no
exit. This is indeed the case for
such people. For them the world
is a prison without bars, a
concentration camp without
barbed wire. The paranoic has
specific persecutors. Someone is
against him. There is a plot on
foot to steal his brains. A machine
is concealed in the wall of his
bedroom which emits mind rays
to soften his brain, 80 The
Divided Self or to send electric
shocks through him while he is
asleep. The person I am
describing feels at this phase
persecuted by reality itself. The
world as it is, and other people as
they are, are the dangers. The
self then seeks by being
unembodied to transcend the
world and hence to be safe. But a
self is liable to develop which
feels it is outside all experience
and activity. It becomes a
vacuum. Everything is there,
outside; nothing is here, inside.
Moreover, the constant dread of
all that is there, of being
overwhelmed, is potentiated
rather than mitigated by the need
to keep the world at bay. Yet the
self may at the same time long
more than anything for
participation in the world. Thus,
its greatest longing is felt as its
greatest weakness and giving in
to this weakness is its greatest
dread, since in participation the
individual fears that his vacuum
will be obliterated, that he will be
engulfed or otherwise lose his
identity, which has come to be
equated with the maintenance of
the transcendence of the self
even though this is a
transcendence in avoid. This
detachment of the self means
that the self is never revealed
directly in the individual's
expressions and actions, nor does
it experience anything
spontaneously or immediately.
The self's relationship to the
other is always at one remove.
The direct and immediate
transactions between the
individual, the other, and the
world, even in such basic
respects as perceiving and
acting, all come to be
meaningless, futile, and false.
One can represent the alternative
state of affairs schematically as
shown opposite. Objects
perceived by the self are
experienced as real. Thoughts
and feelings of which the self is
the agent are alive and are felt to
have point. Actions to which the
self is committed are felt as
genuine. If the individual
delegates all transactions
between himself and the other to
a system within his being which
is not 'him', then the world is
experienced as unreal, and all
that belongs to this system is felt
to be false, futile, and
meaningless. Everyone is subject
to a certain extent at one time or
another to such moods of futility,
meaninglessness, and
purposelessness, but in schizoid
individuals these moods are
particularly insistent. These
moods arise from the fact that the
doors of perception and/or the 82
The Divided Self gates of action
are not in the command of the
self but are being lived and
operated by a false self. The
unrealness of perceptions and the
falsity and meaninglessness of all
activity are the necessary
consequences of perception and
activity being in the command of
a false self- a system partially
dissociated from the 'true' self,
which is, therefore, excluded from
direct participation in the
individual's relatedness with
other persons and the world. A
pseudo-duality is thus
experienced in the individual's
own being. Instead of the
individual meeting the world with
an integral selfhood, he disavows
part of his own being along' with
his disavowal of immediate
attachment to things and people
in the world. This can be
represented schematically as
follows: Instead of (self/body)
other the situation is self
(body-other) The self, therefore, is
precluded from having a direct
relationship with real things and
real people. When this has
happened in patients, one is
witness to the struggle which
ensues to preserve the self's own
sense of its own realness,
aliveness, and identity. In the
first scheme, one has a benign
circle. The reality of the world and
of the self are mutually
potentiated by the direct
relationship between self and
other. In Figure 2, there is a
vicious circle. Every element in
this diagram comes to be
experienced as more and more
unreal and dead. Love is
precluded and dread takes its
place. The final effect is an
overall experience of everything
having come to a stop. Nothing
moves; nothing is alive;
everything is dead, including the
self. The self by its detachment is
precluded from a full experience
of realness and aliveness. What
one might call a creative
relationship with the other, in
which there is mutual enrichment
of the self and the other (benign
circle), is impossible, and an
interaction is substituted which
may seem to operate efficiently
and smoothly for a while but
which has no 'life' in it (sterile
relationship). There is a quasi-it-it
interaction instead of an I-thou
relationship. This interaction is a
dead process. The inner self
seeks to live by certain
(apparently) compensating
advantages. Such a self cherishes
certain ideals. One, which wasThe
Divided Self condition called by
Kierkegaard 'shutupness'. The
individual's actions are not felt as
expressions of his self. His
actions, all that David called his
'personality' and which I have
proposed to call his false-self
system, become dissociated and
partly autonomous. The self is
not felt to participate in the
doings of the false self or selves,
and all its or their actions are felt
to be increasingly false and futile.
The self, on the other hand, shut
up with itself, regards itself as the
'true' self and the persona as
false. The individual complains of
futility, of lack of spontaneity, but
he may be cultivating his lack of
spontaneity and thus aggravating
his sense of futility. He says he is
not real and is outside reality and
not properly alive. Existentially,
he is quite right. The self is
extremely aware of itself, and
observes the false self, usually
highly critically. It is characteristic
of the organization of a false self
or persona, on the other hand,
that one way in which it is usually
incomplete is in its very imperfect
reflective awareness. But the self
may feel itself in danger from the
overall spread of the false-self
system or from one particular
part of it (cf. David's dread of
female impersonation). The
individual in this position is
invariably terrifyingly
'selfconscious ' (see Chapter 7) in
the sense in which this word is
used to mean the exact opposite,
namely, the feeling of being
under observation by the other.
These changes in the relationship
between the different aspects of
the person's relation to himself
are constantly associated with his
inter-personal relationships.
These are complex and never
quite the same from person to
person. The individual's
self-relationship becomes a
pseudo-interpersonal one, and
the self treats the false selves as
though they were other people
whom it depersonalizes. David,
for instance, referring to a part he
played which he found was
disliked, said: 'It had a nasty
tongue.' From within, the self now
looks out at the false things being
said and done and detests the
speaker and doer as though he
were someone else. In all this
there is an attempt to create
relationships to persons and
things within the individual
without recourse to the outer
world of persons and things at
all. The individual is developing a
microcosmos within himself; but,
of course, this autistic, private,
intra-individual 'world' is not a
feasible substitute for the only
world there really is, the shared
The embodied and unembodied
self 75 world. If this were a
feasible project then there would
be no need for psychosis. Such a
schizoid individual in one sense is
trying to be omnipotent by
enclosing within his own being,
without recourse to a creative
relationship with others, modes
of relationship that require the
effective presence to him of other
people and of the outer world. He
would appear to be, in an unreal,
impossible way, all persons and
things to himself. The imagined
advantages are safety for the true
self, isolation and hence freedom
from others, self-sufficiency, and
control. The actual disadvantages
that can be mentioned at this
point are that this project is
impossible and, being a false
hope, leads on to persistent
despair; secondly, a persistent,
haunting sense of futility is the
equally inevitable outcome, since
the hidden shut-up self, in
disowning participation (except,
as David's case, by appearing as
another persona) in the
quasi-autonomous activities of
the falseself systems, is living
only 'mentally'. Moreover, this
shut-up self, being isolated, is
unable to be enriched by outer
experience, and so the whole
inner world comes to be more and
more impoverished, until the
individual may come to feel he is
merely a vacuum. The sense of
being able to do anything and the
feeling of possessing everything
then exist side by side with a
feeling of impotence and
emptiness. The individual who
may at one time have felt
predominantly 'outside' the life
going on there, which he affects
to despise as petty and
commonplace compared to the
richness he has here, inside
himself, now longs to get inside
life again, and get life inside
himself, so dreadful is his inner
deadness. The crucial feature of
the schizoid individual of this type
that we have to understand is the
nature of the anxieties to which
he is subject. We have already
outlined some of the forms these
anxieties take under the terms
engulfment, implosion, and the
dread of losing inner autonomy,
freedom; in short, being turned
from a man with subjectivity to a
thing, a mechanism, a stone, an
it, being petrified. We have yet to
study how these anxieties are
potentiated by the development
of the schizoid organization.
When the self partially abandons
the body and its acts, and
withdraws into mental activity, it
experiences itself as an entity
perhaps localized somewhere in
the body. We have suggested
that 76 The Divided Self this
withdrawal is in part an effort to
preserve its being, since
relationship of any kind with
others is experienced as a threat
to the self's identity. The self feels
safe only in hiding, and isolated.
Such a self can, of course, be
isolated at any time whether
other people are present or not.
But this does not work. No one
feels more 'vulnerable', more
liable to be exposed by the look
of another person than the
schizoid individual. If he is not
acutely aware of being seen by
others ('self-conscious'), he has
temporarily avoided his anxiety
becoming manifest by one or
other of two methods. Either he
turns the other person into a
thing, and depersonalizes or
objectifies his own feelings
towards this thing, or he affects
indifference. The
depersonalization of the person
and/or the attitude of indifference
are closely related but not quite
identical. The depersonalized
person can be used,
manipulated, acted upon. As we
stated above (Chapter 1), the
essential feature of a thing as
opposed to a person is that a
thing has no subjectivity of its
own, and hence can have no
reciprocal intentions. In the
attitude of indifference the person
or thing is treated with
casualness, or callousness, as
though he or it did not matter,
ultimately as though he or it did
not exist. A person minus
subjectivity can still be
important. A thing can still
matter a great deal. Indifference
denies to persons and to things
their significance. Petrification, we
remember, was one of Perseus's
methods of killing his enemies. By
means of the eyes in Medusa's
head, he turned them into
stones. Petrification is one way of
killing. Of course, to feel that
another person is treating or
regarding one not as a person
but as a thing need not itself be
frightening if one is sufficiently
sure of one's own existence.
Thus, being a thing in someone
else's eyes does not represent to
the 'normal' person a catastrophic
threat, but to the schizoid
individual every pair of eyes is in
a Medusa's head which he feels
has power actually to kill or
deaden something precariously
vital in him. He tries therefore to
forestall his own petrification by
turning others into stones. By
doing this he feels he can achieve
some measure of safety.
Generally speaking, the schizoid
individual is not erecting
defences against the loss of a
part of his body. His whole effort
is rather to preserve his self.
This, as we have pointed out, is
pre- The embodied and
unembodied self 77 cariously
established; he is subject to the
dread of his own dissolution into
non-being, into what William
Blake described in the last resort
as 'chaotic non-entity'. His
autonomy is threatened with
engulfment. He has to guard
himself against losing his
subjectivity and sense of being
alive. In so far as he feels empty,
the full, substantial, living reality
of others is an impingement
which is always liable to get out
of hand and become implosive,
threatening to overwhelm and
obliterate his self completely as a
gas will obliterate a vacuum, or as
water will gush in and entirely fill
an empty dam. The schizoid
individual fears a real live
dialectical relationship with real
live people. He can relate himself
only to depersonalized persons,
to phantoms of his own
phantasies (imagos), perhaps to
things, perhaps to animals. We
suggest, therefore, that the
schizoid state we are describing
can be understood as an attempt
to preserve a being that is
precariously structured. We shall
suggest later that the initial
structuralization of being into its
basic elements occurs in early
infancy. In normal circumstances,
this occurs in such a way as to be
so conclusively stable in its basic
elements (for instance, the
continuity of time, the distinction
between the self and not-self,
phantasy and reality), that it can
henceforth be taken for granted:
on this stable base, a
considerable amount of plasticity
can exist in what we call a
person's 'character'. In the
schizoid character structure, on
the other hand, there is an
insecurity in the laying down of
the foundations and a
compensatory rigidity in the
superstructure. If the whole of the
individual's being cannot be
defended, the individual retracts
his lines of defence until he
withdraws within a central
citadel. He is prepared to write off
everything he is, except his 'self'.
But the tragic paradox is that the
more the self is defended in this
way, the more it is destroyed. The
apparent eventual destruction
and dissolution of the self in
schizophrenic conditions is
accomplished not by external
attacks from the enemy (actual
or supposed), from without, but
by the devastation caused by the
inner defensive manoeuvres
themselves. 5 The inner self in
the schizoid condition You can
hold yourself back from the
sufferings of the world, this is
something you are free to do and
is in accord with your nature, but
perhaps precisely this holding
back is the only suffering that you
might be able to avoid. FRANZ
KAFKA In the schizoid condition
here described there is a
persistent scission between the
self and the body. What the
individual regards as his true self
is experienced as more or less
disembodied, and bodily
experience and actions are in turn
felt to be part of the false-self
system. It is now necessary to
consider the two elements in this
split in more detail, and also the
relationship of the one to the
other. First, we consider the
mental or unembodied self. It is
well known that temporary states
of dissociation of the self from the
body occur in normal people. In
general, one can say that it is a
response that appears to be
available to most people who find
themselves enclosed within a
threatening experience from
which there is no physical
escape. Prisoners in concentration
camps tried to feel that way, for
the camp offered no possible way
out either spatially or at the end
of a period of time. The only way
out was by a psychical
withdrawal 'into' one's self and
'out of the body. This dissociation
is characteristically associated
with such thoughts as 'This is like
a dream', 'This seems unreal', 'I
can't believe this is true', 'Nothing
seemed to be touching me', 'I
cannot take it in', 'This is not
happening to me', i.e. with
feelings of estrangement and
derealization. The body may go
on acting in an outwardly normal
way, but inwardly it is felt to be
acting on its own, automatically.
However, despite the
dream-nature or unreality of
experience, and the automatic
nature of action, the self is at the
same time far from 'sleepy';
indeed, it is excessively alert, and
may be thinking and observing
with exceptional lucidity. The
inner self in the schizoid condition
79 The temporary estrangement
of the self from the body may be
represented in dreams. A girl of
nineteen, the date of whose
marriage was fast approaching, a
marriage she had come to dread
for various reasons, dreamed that
she was in the back seat of a car,
which was driving itself. This girl
was not a basically schizoid
person but was reacting by a
schizoid defence to a particular
situation. R. had a dream shortly
before starting treatment. He was
on the footplate of a bus. The bus
had no driver. He jumped off and
the bus went on to crash. One is
tempted to regard a dream he
had after four months of
psychotherapy as a measure of
some change in a desirable
direction. 'I am running after a
bus. Suddenly I'm on the
footplate of the bus, and at the
same time, I'm running after it. I'm
trying to join up with myself on
the bus but I can't entirely catch
up on the bus. I felt frightened at
this.' One could multiply
instances of this common
experience of temporary
dissociation. Sometimes it is
intentionally induced; more
often, it occurs without the
individual's control. But in the
patients here considered, the
splitting is not simply a
temporary reaction to a specific
situation of great danger, which is
reversible when the danger is
past. It is, on the contrary, a basic
orientation to life, and if it is
followed back through their lives
one usually finds that they seem,
in fact, to have emerged from the
early months of infancy with this
split already under way. The
'normal' individual, in a situation
all can see to be threatening to
his being and to offer no real
sense of escape, develops a
schizoid state in trying to get
outside it, if not physically, at
least mentally: he becomes a
mental observer, who looks on,
detached and impassive, at what
his body is doing or what is being
done to his body. If this is so in
the 'normal', it is at least possible
to suppose that the individual
whose abiding mode of
being-in-the-world is of this split
nature is living in what to him, if
not to us, is a world that
threatens his being from all
sides, and from which there is no
exit. This is indeed the case for
such people. For them the world
is a prison without bars, a
concentration camp without
barbed wire. The paranoic has
specific persecutors. Someone is
against him. There is a plot on
foot to steal his brains. A machine
is concealed in the wall of his
bedroom which emits mind rays
to soften his brain, 80 The
Divided Self or to send electric
shocks through him while he is
asleep. The person I am
describing feels at this phase
persecuted by reality itself. The
world as it is, and other people as
they are, are the dangers. The
self then seeks by being
unembodied to transcend the
world and hence to be safe. But a
self is liable to develop which
feels it is outside all experience
and activity. It becomes a
vacuum. Everything is there,
outside; nothing is here, inside.
Moreover, the constant dread of
all that is there, of being
overwhelmed, is potentiated
rather than mitigated by the need
to keep the world at bay. Yet the
self may at the same time long
more than anything for
participation in the world. Thus,
its greatest longing is felt as its
greatest weakness and giving in
to this weakness is its greatest
dread, since in participation the
individual fears that his vacuum
will be obliterated, that he will be
engulfed or otherwise lose his
identity, which has come to be
equated with the maintenance of
the transcendence of the self
even though this is a
transcendence in avoid. This
detachment of the self means
that the self is never revealed
directly in the individual's
expressions and actions, nor does
it experience anything
spontaneously or immediately.
The self's relationship to the
other is always at one remove.
The direct and immediate
transactions between the
individual, the other, and the
world, even in such basic
respects as perceiving and
acting, all come to be
meaningless, futile, and false.
One can represent the alternative
state of affairs schematically as
shown opposite. Objects
perceived by the self are
experienced as real. Thoughts
and feelings of which the self is
the agent are alive and are felt to
have point. Actions to which the
self is committed are felt as
genuine. If the individual
delegates all transactions
between himself and the other to
a system within his being which
is not 'him', then the world is
experienced as unreal, and all
that belongs to this system is felt
to be false, futile, and
meaningless. Everyone is subject
to a certain extent at one time or
another to such moods of futility,
meaninglessness, and
purposelessness, but in schizoid
individuals these moods are
particularly insistent. These
moods arise from the fact that the
doors of perception and/or the 82
The Divided Self gates of action
are not in the command of the
self but are being lived and
operated by a false self. The
unrealness of perceptions and the
falsity and meaninglessness of all
activity are the necessary
consequences of perception and
activity being in the command of
a false self- a system partially
dissociated from the 'true' self,
which is, therefore, excluded from
direct participation in the
individual's relatedness with
other persons and the world. A
pseudo-duality is thus
experienced in the individual's
own being. Instead of the
individual meeting the world with
an integral selfhood, he disavows
part of his own being along' with
his disavowal of immediate
attachment to things and people
in the world. This can be
represented schematically as
follows: Instead of (self/body)
other the situation is self
(body-other) The self, therefore, is
precluded from having a direct
relationship with real things and
real people. When this has
happened in patients, one is
witness to the struggle which
ensues to preserve the self's own
sense of its own realness,
aliveness, and identity. In the
first scheme, one has a benign
circle. The reality of the world and
of the self are mutually
potentiated by the direct
relationship between self and
other. In Figure 2, there is a
vicious circle. Every element in
this diagram comes to be
experienced as more and more
unreal and dead. Love is
precluded and dread takes its
place. The final effect is an
overall experience of everything
having come to a stop. Nothing
moves; nothing is alive;
everything is dead, including the
self. The self by its detachment is
precluded from a full experience
of realness and aliveness. What
one might call a creative
relationship with the other, in
which there is mutual enrichment
of the self and the other (benign
circle), is impossible, and an
interaction is substituted which
may seem to operate efficiently
and smoothly for a while but
which has no 'life' in it (sterile
relationship). There is a quasi-it-it
interaction instead of an I-thou
relationship. This interaction is a
dead process. The inner self
seeks to live by certain
(apparently) compensating
advantages. Such a self cherishes
certain ideals. One, which wasThe
Divided Self condition called by
Kierkegaard 'shutupness'. The
individual's actions are not felt as
expressions of his self. His
actions, all that David called his
'personality' and which I have
proposed to call his false-self
system, become dissociated and
partly autonomous. The self is
not felt to participate in the
doings of the false self or selves,
and all its or their actions are felt
to be increasingly false and futile.
The self, on the other hand, shut
up with itself, regards itself as the
'true' self and the persona as
false. The individual complains of
futility, of lack of spontaneity, but
he may be cultivating his lack of
spontaneity and thus aggravating
his sense of futility. He says he is
not real and is outside reality and
not properly alive. Existentially,
he is quite right. The self is
extremely aware of itself, and
observes the false self, usually
highly critically. It is characteristic
of the organization of a false self
or persona, on the other hand,
that one way in which it is usually
incomplete is in its very imperfect
reflective awareness. But the self
may feel itself in danger from the
overall spread of the false-self
system or from one particular
part of it (cf. David's dread of
female impersonation). The
individual in this position is
invariably terrifyingly
'selfconscious ' (see Chapter 7) in
the sense in which this word is
used to mean the exact opposite,
namely, the feeling of being
under observation by the other.
These changes in the relationship
between the different aspects of
the person's relation to himself
are constantly associated with his
inter-personal relationships.
These are complex and never
quite the same from person to
person. The individual's
self-relationship becomes a
pseudo-interpersonal one, and
the self treats the false selves as
though they were other people
whom it depersonalizes. David,
for instance, referring to a part he
played which he found was
disliked, said: 'It had a nasty
tongue.' From within, the self now
looks out at the false things being
said and done and detests the
speaker and doer as though he
were someone else. In all this
there is an attempt to create
relationships to persons and
things within the individual
without recourse to the outer
world of persons and things at
all. The individual is developing a
microcosmos within himself; but,
of course, this autistic, private,
intra-individual 'world' is not a
feasible substitute for the only
world there really is, the shared
The embodied and unembodied
self 75 world. If this were a
feasible project then there would
be no need for psychosis. Such a
schizoid individual in one sense is
trying to be omnipotent by
enclosing within his own being,
without recourse to a creative
relationship with others, modes
of relationship that require the
effective presence to him of other
people and of the outer world. He
would appear to be, in an unreal,
impossible way, all persons and
things to himself. The imagined
advantages are safety for the true
self, isolation and hence freedom
from others, self-sufficiency, and
control. The actual disadvantages
that can be mentioned at this
point are that this project is
impossible and, being a false
hope, leads on to persistent
despair; secondly, a persistent,
haunting sense of futility is the
equally inevitable outcome, since
the hidden shut-up self, in
disowning participation (except,
as David's case, by appearing as
another persona) in the
quasi-autonomous activities of
the falseself systems, is living
only 'mentally'. Moreover, this
shut-up self, being isolated, is
unable to be enriched by outer
experience, and so the whole
inner world comes to be more and
more impoverished, until the
individual may come to feel he is
merely a vacuum. The sense of
being able to do anything and the
feeling of possessing everything
then exist side by side with a
feeling of impotence and
emptiness. The individual who
may at one time have felt
predominantly 'outside' the life
going on there, which he affects
to despise as petty and
commonplace compared to the
richness he has here, inside
himself, now longs to get inside
life again, and get life inside
himself, so dreadful is his inner
deadness. The crucial feature of
the schizoid individual of this type
that we have to understand is the
nature of the anxieties to which
he is subject. We have already
outlined some of the forms these
anxieties take under the terms
engulfment, implosion, and the
dread of losing inner autonomy,
freedom; in short, being turned
from a man with subjectivity to a
thing, a mechanism, a stone, an
it, being petrified. We have yet to
study how these anxieties are
potentiated by the development
of the schizoid organization.
When the self partially abandons
the body and its acts, and
withdraws into mental activity, it
experiences itself as an entity
perhaps localized somewhere in
the body. We have suggested
that 76 The Divided Self this
withdrawal is in part an effort to
preserve its being, since
relationship of any kind with
others is experienced as a threat
to the self's identity. The self feels
safe only in hiding, and isolated.
Such a self can, of course, be
isolated at any time whether
other people are present or not.
But this does not work. No one
feels more 'vulnerable', more
liable to be exposed by the look
of another person than the
schizoid individual. If he is not
acutely aware of being seen by
others ('self-conscious'), he has
temporarily avoided his anxiety
becoming manifest by one or
other of two methods. Either he
turns the other person into a
thing, and depersonalizes or
objectifies his own feelings
towards this thing, or he affects
indifference. The
depersonalization of the person
and/or the attitude of indifference
are closely related but not quite
identical. The depersonalized
person can be used,
manipulated, acted upon. As we
stated above (Chapter 1), the
essential feature of a thing as
opposed to a person is that a
thing has no subjectivity of its
own, and hence can have no
reciprocal intentions. In the
attitude of indifference the person
or thing is treated with
casualness, or callousness, as
though he or it did not matter,
ultimately as though he or it did
not exist. A person minus
subjectivity can still be
important. A thing can still
matter a great deal. Indifference
denies to persons and to things
their significance. Petrification, we
remember, was one of Perseus's
methods of killing his enemies. By
means of the eyes in Medusa's
head, he turned them into
stones. Petrification is one way of
killing. Of course, to feel that
another person is treating or
regarding one not as a person
but as a thing need not itself be
frightening if one is sufficiently
sure of one's own existence.
Thus, being a thing in someone
else's eyes does not represent to
the 'normal' person a catastrophic
threat, but to the schizoid
individual every pair of eyes is in
a Medusa's head which he feels
has power actually to kill or
deaden something precariously
vital in him. He tries therefore to
forestall his own petrification by
turning others into stones. By
doing this he feels he can achieve
some measure of safety.
Generally speaking, the schizoid
individual is not erecting
defences against the loss of a
part of his body. His whole effort
is rather to preserve his self.
This, as we have pointed out, is
pre- The embodied and
unembodied self 77 cariously
established; he is subject to the
dread of his own dissolution into
non-being, into what William
Blake described in the last resort
as 'chaotic non-entity'. His
autonomy is threatened with
engulfment. He has to guard
himself against losing his
subjectivity and sense of being
alive. In so far as he feels empty,
the full, substantial, living reality
of others is an impingement
which is always liable to get out
of hand and become implosive,
threatening to overwhelm and
obliterate his self completely as a
gas will obliterate a vacuum, or as
water will gush in and entirely fill
an empty dam. The schizoid
individual fears a real live
dialectical relationship with real
live people. He can relate himself
only to depersonalized persons,
to phantoms of his own
phantasies (imagos), perhaps to
things, perhaps to animals. We
suggest, therefore, that the
schizoid state we are describing
can be understood as an attempt
to preserve a being that is
precariously structured. We shall
suggest later that the initial
structuralization of being into its
basic elements occurs in early
infancy. In normal circumstances,
this occurs in such a way as to be
so conclusively stable in its basic
elements (for instance, the
continuity of time, the distinction
between the self and not-self,
phantasy and reality), that it can
henceforth be taken for granted:
on this stable base, a
considerable amount of plasticity
can exist in what we call a
person's 'character'. In the
schizoid character structure, on
the other hand, there is an
insecurity in the laying down of
the foundations and a
compensatory rigidity in the
superstructure. If the whole of the
individual's being cannot be
defended, the individual retracts
his lines of defence until he
withdraws within a central
citadel. He is prepared to write off
everything he is, except his 'self'.
But the tragic paradox is that the
more the self is defended in this
way, the more it is destroyed. The
apparent eventual destruction
and dissolution of the self in
schizophrenic conditions is
accomplished not by external
attacks from the enemy (actual
or supposed), from without, but
by the devastation caused by the
inner defensive manoeuvres
themselves. 5 The inner self in
the schizoid condition You can
hold yourself back from the
sufferings of the world, this is
something you are free to do and
is in accord with your nature, but
perhaps precisely this holding
back is the only suffering that you
might be able to avoid. FRANZ
KAFKA In the schizoid condition
here described there is a
persistent scission between the
self and the body. What the
individual regards as his true self
is experienced as more or less
disembodied, and bodily
experience and actions are in turn
felt to be part of the false-self
system. It is now necessary to
consider the two elements in this
split in more detail, and also the
relationship of the one to the
other. First, we consider the
mental or unembodied self. It is
well known that temporary states
of dissociation of the self from the
body occur in normal people. In
general, one can say that it is a
response that appears to be
available to most people who find
themselves enclosed within a
threatening experience from
which there is no physical
escape. Prisoners in concentration
camps tried to feel that way, for
the camp offered no possible way
out either spatially or at the end
of a period of time. The only way
out was by a psychical
withdrawal 'into' one's self and
'out of the body. This dissociation
is characteristically associated
with such thoughts as 'This is like
a dream', 'This seems unreal', 'I
can't believe this is true', 'Nothing
seemed to be touching me', 'I
cannot take it in', 'This is not
happening to me', i.e. with
feelings of estrangement and
derealization. The body may go
on acting in an outwardly normal
way, but inwardly it is felt to be
acting on its own, automatically.
However, despite the
dream-nature or unreality of
experience, and the automatic
nature of action, the self is at the
same time far from 'sleepy';
indeed, it is excessively alert, and
may be thinking and observing
with exceptional lucidity. The
inner self in the schizoid condition
79 The temporary estrangement
of the self from the body may be
represented in dreams. A girl of
nineteen, the date of whose
marriage was fast approaching, a
marriage she had come to dread
for various reasons, dreamed that
she was in the back seat of a car,
which was driving itself. This girl
was not a basically schizoid
person but was reacting by a
schizoid defence to a particular
situation. R. had a dream shortly
before starting treatment. He was
on the footplate of a bus. The bus
had no driver. He jumped off and
the bus went on to crash. One is
tempted to regard a dream he
had after four months of
psychotherapy as a measure of
some change in a desirable
direction. 'I am running after a
bus. Suddenly I'm on the
footplate of the bus, and at the
same time, I'm running after it. I'm
trying to join up with myself on
the bus but I can't entirely catch
up on the bus. I felt frightened at
this.' One could multiply
instances of this common
experience of temporary
dissociation. Sometimes it is
intentionally induced; more
often, it occurs without the
individual's control. But in the
patients here considered, the
splitting is not simply a
temporary reaction to a specific
situation of great danger, which is
reversible when the danger is
past. It is, on the contrary, a basic
orientation to life, and if it is
followed back through their lives
one usually finds that they seem,
in fact, to have emerged from the
early months of infancy with this
split already under way. The
'normal' individual, in a situation
all can see to be threatening to
his being and to offer no real
sense of escape, develops a
schizoid state in trying to get
outside it, if not physically, at
least mentally: he becomes a
mental observer, who looks on,
detached and impassive, at what
his body is doing or what is being
done to his body. If this is so in
the 'normal', it is at least possible
to suppose that the individual
whose abiding mode of
being-in-the-world is of this split
nature is living in what to him, if
not to us, is a world that
threatens his being from all
sides, and from which there is no
exit. This is indeed the case for
such people. For them the world
is a prison without bars, a
concentration camp without
barbed wire. The paranoic has
specific persecutors. Someone is
against him. There is a plot on
foot to steal his brains. A machine
is concealed in the wall of his
bedroom which emits mind rays
to soften his brain, 80 The
Divided Self or to send electric
shocks through him while he is
asleep. The person I am
describing feels at this phase
persecuted by reality itself. The
world as it is, and other people as
they are, are the dangers. The
self then seeks by being
unembodied to transcend the
world and hence to be safe. But a
self is liable to develop which
feels it is outside all experience
and activity. It becomes a
vacuum. Everything is there,
outside; nothing is here, inside.
Moreover, the constant dread of
all that is there, of being
overwhelmed, is potentiated
rather than mitigated by the need
to keep the world at bay. Yet the
self may at the same time long
more than anything for
participation in the world. Thus,
its greatest longing is felt as its
greatest weakness and giving in
to this weakness is its greatest
dread, since in participation the
individual fears that his vacuum
will be obliterated, that he will be
engulfed or otherwise lose his
identity, which has come to be
equated with the maintenance of
the transcendence of the self
even though this is a
transcendence in avoid. This
detachment of the self means
that the self is never revealed
directly in the individual's
expressions and actions, nor does
it experience anything
spontaneously or immediately.
The self's relationship to the
other is always at one remove.
The direct and immediate
transactions between the
individual, the other, and the
world, even in such basic
respects as perceiving and
acting, all come to be
meaningless, futile, and false.
One can represent the alternative
state of affairs schematically as
shown opposite. Objects
perceived by the self are
experienced as real. Thoughts
and feelings of which the self is
the agent are alive and are felt to
have point. Actions to which the
self is committed are felt as
genuine. If the individual
delegates all transactions
between himself and the other to
a system within his being which
is not 'him', then the world is
experienced as unreal, and all
that belongs to this system is felt
to be false, futile, and
meaningless. Everyone is subject
to a certain extent at one time or
another to such moods of futility,
meaninglessness, and
purposelessness, but in schizoid
individuals these moods are
particularly insistent. These
moods arise from the fact that the
doors of perception and/or the 82
The Divided Self gates of action
are not in the command of the
self but are being lived and
operated by a false self. The
unrealness of perceptions and the
falsity and meaninglessness of all
activity are the necessary
consequences of perception and
activity being in the command of
a false self- a system partially
dissociated from the 'true' self,
which is, therefore, excluded from
direct participation in the
individual's relatedness with
other persons and the world. A
pseudo-duality is thus
experienced in the individual's
own being. Instead of the
individual meeting the world with
an integral selfhood, he disavows
part of his own being along' with
his disavowal of immediate
attachment to things and people
in the world. This can be
represented schematically as
follows: Instead of (self/body)
other the situation is self
(body-other) The self, therefore, is
precluded from having a direct
relationship with real things and
real people. When this has
happened in patients, one is
witness to the struggle which
ensues to preserve the self's own
sense of its own realness,
aliveness, and identity. In the
first scheme, one has a benign
circle. The reality of the world and
of the self are mutually
potentiated by the direct
relationship between self and
other. In Figure 2, there is a
vicious circle. Every element in
this diagram comes to be
experienced as more and more
unreal and dead. Love is
precluded and dread takes its
place. The final effect is an
overall experience of everything
having come to a stop. Nothing
moves; nothing is alive;
everything is dead, including the
self. The self by its detachment is
precluded from a full experience
of realness and aliveness. What
one might call a creative
relationship with the other, in
which there is mutual enrichment
of the self and the other (benign
circle), is impossible, and an
interaction is substituted which
may seem to operate efficiently
and smoothly for a while but
which has no 'life' in it (sterile
relationship). There is a quasi-it-it
interaction instead of an I-thou
relationship. This interaction is a
dead process. The inner self
seeks to live by certain
(apparently) compensating
advantages. Such a self cherishes
certain ideals. One, which wasThe
Divided Self condition called by
Kierkegaard 'shutupness'. The
individual's actions are not felt as
expressions of his self. His
actions, all that David called his
'personality' and which I have
proposed to call his false-self
system, become dissociated and
partly autonomous. The self is
not felt to participate in the
doings of the false self or selves,
and all its or their actions are felt
to be increasingly false and futile.
The self, on the other hand, shut
up with itself, regards itself as the
'true' self and the persona as
false. The individual complains of
futility, of lack of spontaneity, but
he may be cultivating his lack of
spontaneity and thus aggravating
his sense of futility. He says he is
not real and is outside reality and
not properly alive. Existentially,
he is quite right. The self is
extremely aware of itself, and
observes the false self, usually
highly critically. It is characteristic
of the organization of a false self
or persona, on the other hand,
that one way in which it is usually
incomplete is in its very imperfect
reflective awareness. But the self
may feel itself in danger from the
overall spread of the false-self
system or from one particular
part of it (cf. David's dread of
female impersonation). The
individual in this position is
invariably terrifyingly
'selfconscious ' (see Chapter 7) in
the sense in which this word is
used to mean the exact opposite,
namely, the feeling of being
under observation by the other.
These changes in the relationship
between the different aspects of
the person's relation to himself
are constantly associated with his
inter-personal relationships.
These are complex and never
quite the same from person to
person. The individual's
self-relationship becomes a
pseudo-interpersonal one, and
the self treats the false selves as
though they were other people
whom it depersonalizes. David,
for instance, referring to a part he
played which he found was
disliked, said: 'It had a nasty
tongue.' From within, the self now
looks out at the false things being
said and done and detests the
speaker and doer as though he
were someone else. In all this
there is an attempt to create
relationships to persons and
things within the individual
without recourse to the outer
world of persons and things at
all. The individual is developing a
microcosmos within himself; but,
of course, this autistic, private,
intra-individual 'world' is not a
feasible substitute for the only
world there really is, the shared
The embodied and unembodied
self 75 world. If this were a
feasible project then there would
be no need for psychosis. Such a
schizoid individual in one sense is
trying to be omnipotent by
enclosing within his own being,
without recourse to a creative
relationship with others, modes
of relationship that require the
effective presence to him of other
people and of the outer world. He
would appear to be, in an unreal,
impossible way, all persons and
things to himself. The imagined
advantages are safety for the true
self, isolation and hence freedom
from others, self-sufficiency, and
control. The actual disadvantages
that can be mentioned at this
point are that this project is
impossible and, being a false
hope, leads on to persistent
despair; secondly, a persistent,
haunting sense of futility is the
equally inevitable outcome, since
the hidden shut-up self, in
disowning participation (except,
as David's case, by appearing as
another persona) in the
quasi-autonomous activities of
the falseself systems, is living
only 'mentally'. Moreover, this
shut-up self, being isolated, is
unable to be enriched by outer
experience, and so the whole
inner world comes to be more and
more impoverished, until the
individual may come to feel he is
merely a vacuum. The sense of
being able to do anything and the
feeling of possessing everything
then exist side by side with a
feeling of impotence and
emptiness. The individual who
may at one time have felt
predominantly 'outside' the life
going on there, which he affects
to despise as petty and
commonplace compared to the
richness he has here, inside
himself, now longs to get inside
life again, and get life inside
himself, so dreadful is his inner
deadness. The crucial feature of
the schizoid individual of this type
that we have to understand is the
nature of the anxieties to which
he is subject. We have already
outlined some of the forms these
anxieties take under the terms
engulfment, implosion, and the
dread of losing inner autonomy,
freedom; in short, being turned
from a man with subjectivity to a
thing, a mechanism, a stone, an
it, being petrified. We have yet to
study how these anxieties are
potentiated by the development
of the schizoid organization.
When the self partially abandons
the body and its acts, and
withdraws into mental activity, it
experiences itself as an entity
perhaps localized somewhere in
the body. We have suggested
that 76 The Divided Self this
withdrawal is in part an effort to
preserve its being, since
relationship of any kind with
others is experienced as a threat
to the self's identity. The self feels
safe only in hiding, and isolated.
Such a self can, of course, be
isolated at any time whether
other people are present or not.
But this does not work. No one
feels more 'vulnerable', more
liable to be exposed by the look
of another person than the
schizoid individual. If he is not
acutely aware of being seen by
others ('self-conscious'), he has
temporarily avoided his anxiety
becoming manifest by one or
other of two methods. Either he
turns the other person into a
thing, and depersonalizes or
objectifies his own feelings
towards this thing, or he affects
indifference. The
depersonalization of the person
and/or the attitude of indifference
are closely related but not quite
identical. The depersonalized
person can be used,
manipulated, acted upon. As we
stated above (Chapter 1), the
essential feature of a thing as
opposed to a person is that a
thing has no subjectivity of its
own, and hence can have no
reciprocal intentions. In the
attitude of indifference the person
or thing is treated with
casualness, or callousness, as
though he or it did not matter,
ultimately as though he or it did
not exist. A person minus
subjectivity can still be
important. A thing can still
matter a great deal. Indifference
denies to persons and to things
their significance. Petrification, we
remember, was one of Perseus's
methods of killing his enemies. By
means of the eyes in Medusa's
head, he turned them into
stones. Petrification is one way of
killing. Of course, to feel that
another person is treating or
regarding one not as a person
but as a thing need not itself be
frightening if one is sufficiently
sure of one's own existence.
Thus, being a thing in someone
else's eyes does not represent to
the 'normal' person a catastrophic
threat, but to the schizoid
individual every pair of eyes is in
a Medusa's head which he feels
has power actually to kill or
deaden something precariously
vital in him. He tries therefore to
forestall his own petrification by
turning others into stones. By
doing this he feels he can achieve
some measure of safety.
Generally speaking, the schizoid
individual is not erecting
defences against the loss of a
part of his body. His whole effort
is rather to preserve his self.
This, as we have pointed out, is
pre- The embodied and
unembodied self 77 cariously
established; he is subject to the
dread of his own dissolution into
non-being, into what William
Blake described in the last resort
as 'chaotic non-entity'. His
autonomy is threatened with
engulfment. He has to guard
himself against losing his
subjectivity and sense of being
alive. In so far as he feels empty,
the full, substantial, living reality
of others is an impingement
which is always liable to get out
of hand and become implosive,
threatening to overwhelm and
obliterate his self completely as a
gas will obliterate a vacuum, or as
water will gush in and entirely fill
an empty dam. The schizoid
individual fears a real live
dialectical relationship with real
live people. He can relate himself
only to depersonalized persons,
to phantoms of his own
phantasies (imagos), perhaps to
things, perhaps to animals. We
suggest, therefore, that the
schizoid state we are describing
can be understood as an attempt
to preserve a being that is
precariously structured. We shall
suggest later that the initial
structuralization of being into its
basic elements occurs in early
infancy. In normal circumstances,
this occurs in such a way as to be
so conclusively stable in its basic
elements (for instance, the
continuity of time, the distinction
between the self and not-self,
phantasy and reality), that it can
henceforth be taken for granted:
on this stable base, a
considerable amount of plasticity
can exist in what we call a
person's 'character'. In the
schizoid character structure, on
the other hand, there is an
insecurity in the laying down of
the foundations and a
compensatory rigidity in the
superstructure. If the whole of the
individual's being cannot be
defended, the individual retracts
his lines of defence until he
withdraws within a central
citadel. He is prepared to write off
everything he is, except his 'self'.
But the tragic paradox is that the
more the self is defended in this
way, the more it is destroyed. The
apparent eventual destruction
and dissolution of the self in
schizophrenic conditions is
accomplished not by external
attacks from the enemy (actual
or supposed), from without, but
by the devastation caused by the
inner defensive manoeuvres
themselves. 5 The inner self in
the schizoid condition You can
hold yourself back from the
sufferings of the world, this is
something you are free to do and
is in accord with your nature, but
perhaps precisely this holding
back is the only suffering that you
might be able to avoid. FRANZ
KAFKA In the schizoid condition
here described there is a
persistent scission between the
self and the body. What the
individual regards as his true self
is experienced as more or less
disembodied, and bodily
experience and actions are in turn
felt to be part of the false-self
system. It is now necessary to
consider the two elements in this
split in more detail, and also the
relationship of the one to the
other. First, we consider the
mental or unembodied self. It is
well known that temporary states
of dissociation of the self from the
body occur in normal people. In
general, one can say that it is a
response that appears to be
available to most people who find
themselves enclosed within a
threatening experience from
which there is no physical
escape. Prisoners in concentration
camps tried to feel that way, for
the camp offered no possible way
out either spatially or at the end
of a period of time. The only way
out was by a psychical
withdrawal 'into' one's self and
'out of the body. This dissociation
is characteristically associated
with such thoughts as 'This is like
a dream', 'This seems unreal', 'I
can't believe this is true', 'Nothing
seemed to be touching me', 'I
cannot take it in', 'This is not
happening to me', i.e. with
feelings of estrangement and
derealization. The body may go
on acting in an outwardly normal
way, but inwardly it is felt to be
acting on its own, automatically.
However, despite the
dream-nature or unreality of
experience, and the automatic
nature of action, the self is at the
same time far from 'sleepy';
indeed, it is excessively alert, and
may be thinking and observing
with exceptional lucidity. The
inner self in the schizoid condition
79 The temporary estrangement
of the self from the body may be
represented in dreams. A girl of
nineteen, the date of whose
marriage was fast approaching, a
marriage she had come to dread
for various reasons, dreamed that
she was in the back seat of a car,
which was driving itself. This girl
was not a basically schizoid
person but was reacting by a
schizoid defence to a particular
situation. R. had a dream shortly
before starting treatment. He was
on the footplate of a bus. The bus
had no driver. He jumped off and
the bus went on to crash. One is
tempted to regard a dream he
had after four months of
psychotherapy as a measure of
some change in a desirable
direction. 'I am running after a
bus. Suddenly I'm on the
footplate of the bus, and at the
same time, I'm running after it. I'm
trying to join up with myself on
the bus but I can't entirely catch
up on the bus. I felt frightened at
this.' One could multiply
instances of this common
experience of temporary
dissociation. Sometimes it is
intentionally induced; more
often, it occurs without the
individual's control. But in the
patients here considered, the
splitting is not simply a
temporary reaction to a specific
situation of great danger, which is
reversible when the danger is
past. It is, on the contrary, a basic
orientation to life, and if it is
followed back through their lives
one usually finds that they seem,
in fact, to have emerged from the
early months of infancy with this
split already under way. The
'normal' individual, in a situation
all can see to be threatening to
his being and to offer no real
sense of escape, develops a
schizoid state in trying to get
outside it, if not physically, at
least mentally: he becomes a
mental observer, who looks on,
detached and impassive, at what
his body is doing or what is being
done to his body. If this is so in
the 'normal', it is at least possible
to suppose that the individual
whose abiding mode of
being-in-the-world is of this split
nature is living in what to him, if
not to us, is a world that
threatens his being from all
sides, and from which there is no
exit. This is indeed the case for
such people. For them the world
is a prison without bars, a
concentration camp without
barbed wire. The paranoic has
specific persecutors. Someone is
against him. There is a plot on
foot to steal his brains. A machine
is concealed in the wall of his
bedroom which emits mind rays
to soften his brain, 80 The
Divided Self or to send electric
shocks through him while he is
asleep. The person I am
describing feels at this phase
persecuted by reality itself. The
world as it is, and other people as
they are, are the dangers. The
self then seeks by being
unembodied to transcend the
world and hence to be safe. But a
self is liable to develop which
feels it is outside all experience
and activity. It becomes a
vacuum. Everything is there,
outside; nothing is here, inside.
Moreover, the constant dread of
all that is there, of being
overwhelmed, is potentiated
rather than mitigated by the need
to keep the world at bay. Yet the
self may at the same time long
more than anything for
participation in the world. Thus,
its greatest longing is felt as its
greatest weakness and giving in
to this weakness is its greatest
dread, since in participation the
individual fears that his vacuum
will be obliterated, that he will be
engulfed or otherwise lose his
identity, which has come to be
equated with the maintenance of
the transcendence of the self
even though this is a
transcendence in avoid. This
detachment of the self means
that the self is never revealed
directly in the individual's
expressions and actions, nor does
it experience anything
spontaneously or immediately.
The self's relationship to the
other is always at one remove.
The direct and immediate
transactions between the
individual, the other, and the
world, even in such basic
respects as perceiving and
acting, all come to be
meaningless, futile, and false.
One can represent the alternative
state of affairs schematically as
shown opposite. Objects
perceived by the self are
experienced as real. Thoughts
and feelings of which the self is
the agent are alive and are felt to
have point. Actions to which the
self is committed are felt as
genuine. If the individual
delegates all transactions
between himself and the other to
a system within his being which
is not 'him', then the world is
experienced as unreal, and all
that belongs to this system is felt
to be false, futile, and
meaningless. Everyone is subject
to a certain extent at one time or
another to such moods of futility,
meaninglessness, and
purposelessness, but in schizoid
individuals these moods are
particularly insistent. These
moods arise from the fact that the
doors of perception and/or the 82
The Divided Self gates of action
are not in the command of the
self but are being lived and
operated by a false self. The
unrealness of perceptions and the
falsity and meaninglessness of all
activity are the necessary
consequences of perception and
activity being in the command of
a false self- a system partially
dissociated from the 'true' self,
which is, therefore, excluded from
direct participation in the
individual's relatedness with
other persons and the world. A
pseudo-duality is thus
experienced in the individual's
own being. Instead of the
individual meeting the world with
an integral selfhood, he disavows
part of his own being along' with
his disavowal of immediate
attachment to things and people
in the world. This can be
represented schematically as
follows: Instead of (self/body)
other the situation is self
(body-other) The self, therefore, is
precluded from having a direct
relationship with real things and
real people. When this has
happened in patients, one is
witness to the struggle which
ensues to preserve the self's own
sense of its own realness,
aliveness, and identity. In the
first scheme, one has a benign
circle. The reality of the world and
of the self are mutually
potentiated by the direct
relationship between self and
other. In Figure 2, there is a
vicious circle. Every element in
this diagram comes to be
experienced as more and more
unreal and dead. Love is
precluded and dread takes its
place. The final effect is an
overall experience of everything
having come to a stop. Nothing
moves; nothing is alive;
everything is dead, including the
self. The self by its detachment is
precluded from a full experience
of realness and aliveness. What
one might call a creative
relationship with the other, in
which there is mutual enrichment
of the self and the other (benign
circle), is impossible, and an
interaction is substituted which
may seem to operate efficiently
and smoothly for a while but
which has no 'life' in it (sterile
relationship). There is a quasi-it-it
interaction instead of an I-thou
relationship. This interaction is a
dead process. The inner self
seeks to live by certain
(apparently) compensating
advantages. Such a self cherishes
certain ideals. One, which was
In his first book, The Divided Self
(1960), british psychiatric Ronald
Laing theorized that ontological
insecurity (insecurity about one's
existence) prompts a defensive
reaction in which the self splits
into separate components, thus
generating the psychotic
symptoms associated with
dissociative disorders. According
to Laing, dissociated individuals,
when fighting for their (sense of)
existence, create systems of
(false) selves, to which they can
resort to in order to shield their
(true) self, and prevent this from
disappearing.
In The Divided Self the word 'self'
occurs 1261 times, in a variety of
different constructs. This
multiplicity of selves is a lexical
by-product of the ideas presented
in the book: in some sense, The
Divided Self has a quite
developed 'system of selves'. This
webpage is a typographic
transposition of the process
described by Laing: it substitutes
each self of The Divided Self with
another self from the system of
selves of The Divided Self,
endlessly. In theory, if the
webpage runs long enough, at
some point The Divided Self will
converge to one
unique self - the most common self.
This page works best in Firefox and
it needs JavaScript enabled. To close this dialogue, click
here or anywhere
outside of this box. To read more
about the context of this piece, and
about the word 'self' click
here